• Nem Talált Eredményt

Critical Relations of Crowns in Critical Times of Coronavirus Depression

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Ossza meg "Critical Relations of Crowns in Critical Times of Coronavirus Depression"

Copied!
13
0
0

Teljes szövegt

(1)

https://doi.org/10.1007/s11083-021-09571-6

Critical Relations of Crowns in Critical Times of Coronavirus Depression

Ad ´am Kunos´ 1 ·Mikl ´os Mar ´oti1·L ´aszl ´o Z ´adori1,2

Received: 1 July 2020 / Accepted: 4 June 2021 /

©The Author(s) 2021

Abstract

The critical relations are the building blocks of the relational clone of a relational structure with respect to the relational operations intersection and direct product. In this paper we describe the critical relations of crowns. As a consequence, we obtain that the subpower membership problem for any crown is polynomial-time solvable.

Keywords Poset·Crown·Clone·Finitely generated·Obstruction·Critical relation· Subpower membership problem

1 Introduction

The relational structures in this note are assumed to be always finite. Acrownis a height 1 poset whose comparabilty graph is a cycle, see Fig.1.

Letmdenotem-element antichain and+the linear sum of posets. Let P =1+2+P+2+1

wherePis a poset, and letT =2. In his seminal paper [10] Tardos proved that the clone of the eight element posetT is not finitely generated. Following the terminology in [8], we call the posets of the formC whereC is a crownlocked crowns, see Fig.2.

The research of authors was supported by the grants TUDFO/47138-1/2019-ITM and NKFIH-1279-2/2020 of the Ministry for Innovation and Technology, Hungary, the EU-funded Hungarian grant EFOP-3.6.2-16-2017-00015, and the NKFIH grants K115518 and K128042. The third author was also supported by the Alfr´ed R´enyi Institute of Mathematics, ELKH, Hungary.

Ad´am Kunos´

akunos@math.u-szeged.hu Mikl´os Mar´oti

mmaroti@math.u-szeged.hu L´aszl´o Z´adori

zadori@math.u-szeged.hu

1 Bolyai Institute, University of Szeged, Szeged, Hungary

2 Alfr´ed R´enyi Institute of Mathematics, Budapest, Hungary

(2)

Fig. 1 Some crowns of small cardinality

It is an open question related to Tardos’s result whether the clone of every locked crown is non-finitely generated. The positive answer to this question would be somewhat surpris- ing at the first sight, since Demetrovics and R´onyai have proved in [3] that the clone of monotone operations of any crown is finitely generated. However, from results of the third author in [13] it follows that the clone ofC is non-finitely generated ifC is the four ele- ment crown. The proof of this fact in [13] is reduced to Tardos’s original proof for the poset T. Unfortunately, we are not able to use Tardos’s method to decide whether the clone ofC is finitely generated or not ifC has at least six elements. One of the reasons why Tardos’s proof works is that the extendibility of a partial map from a finite power ofT toT can be easily decided by checking some minimal non-extendible configurations called obstruc- tions. The obstructions have a very simple structure forT, but they are unwieldy forC whereC is a crown. A possible cause for the latter is that the decision problemExt(C) intro- duced in the next paragraph isNP-complete for any crownC. To circumvent this problem we plan to use the critical relations ofC instead of its obstructions to verify the extendibil- ity of a partial map from a finite power ofCtoC. The obstructions ofC are easily obtained from the obstructions ofC, the latter ones have no tangible description, though, as we have mentioned. At present, we do not know an easy way to get the critical relations ofC from the critical relations ofC, but in this note we at least give a simple description of the critical relations of any crownC. We hope that this leads to a description of the critical relations of C and, eventually, to a decision whether the clone ofC is finitely generated.

In [7], Larose and the third author introduced a decision problem called theextendibility problemExt(P)for a finite poset P: given a finite posetQand a partial mapffromQto P, decide whetherfextends to a monotone total map fromQtoP. We define thegraph off to be the set{(h, f (h)) : h ∈Dom(f )}. So an input ofExt(P) is the pair formed by a posetQand the graph off. It is easy to see thatExt(P) is in the complexity class NP. Moreover, Pratt and Tiuryn proved in [9] thatSat(C), a polynomial-time equivalent of Ext(C), isNP-complete ifC is a crown. ThusExt(C) isNP-complete ifC is a crown. In [7], this result was extended for other posets characterized by an algebraic condition.

Fig. 2 PosetT and some locked crowns of small cardinality

(3)

When studying finite generability for the clone of a finite posetP, often an other kind of extendibility question occurs: given a powerPnofPand a partial mapffromPntoP, decide whetherf extends to a monotone total map fromPntoP. We call this problem therestricted extendibility problem for P and denote it byRExt(P). Thus, an input of this problem is the pair formed by the posetPnand the graph off. Clearly,RExt(P) is a polynomial-time reducible toExt(P), so it is inNP.

Anorder-primal algebra related to a posetPis an algebra whose base set equals that ofPand whose term operations coincide with the monotone operations ofP.

We consider another problem, a variant of the restricted extendibility problem. The new problem is called thesubpower membership problemSMP(P): given a partial mapffrom PntoP, decide whetherf extends to a monotone total map fromPntoP. Thus, an input of this problem is just the graph off. Notice that the subpower membership problem is thriftier with the sizes of the inputs than the restricted extendibility problem. It is evident thatRExt(P) is polynomial-time reducible toSMP(P).

Let us suppose now that an input ofSMP(P) is given by the list of pairs(hi, f (hi)), 1ik, wherehiruns through the domain offinPn. Alternatively, we may conceive this list as an(n+1)-element set ofk-tuples where thej-thk-tuple,jn, is the tuple determined by thej-th coordinates of thehiand the(n+1)-stk-tuple is(f (h1), . . . , f (hk)), and then the question ofSMP(P) becomes whether the subalgebra generated by the firstntuples in thek-th power of an order-primal algebra related toPcontains the(n+1)-stk-tuple. The study of these types of problems was first suggested by Willard, see [11], in an algebraic and more general setting. Since then, the research in this area has become a burgeoning branch of mathematics, see [2] for further details and references on the subpower membership problem.

In the proof of the characterization of critical relations of crowns, one of the main tools is a result of Demetrovics and R´onyai in [3] that states that every monotone surjective operation of a crown is essentially unary. As a consequence of our result, we also prove that SMP(C), and henceRExt(C), is solvable in polynomial time ifC is a crown. This gives sharp contrast between the complexities of the two decision problems Ext(P) and RExt(P). We do not know the answer to the question if there is a finite posetPfor which RExt(P) isNP-complete.

2 Critical Relations and Obstructions of Relational Structures

In this section we introduce some basic definitions and prove some general claims on critical relations and obstructions of finite structures. These statements will be applied in the later sections when studying the critical relations of crowns.

LetRbe a relational structure. We denote then-thpowerofRbyRn. The relational structureRnhas the same type asR. Its base set isRnwhereRis the base set ofR. Each of itsk-ary relationsρRnis obtained from ak-ary relationρRofRby

(r1, . . . , rk)ρRn

if and only if all of thek-tuples defined coordinatewise from then-tuplesr1, . . . , rk are in ρR.

LetS be a relational structure of the same type asR. We say that a mapf :SRis ahomomorphismfromS toRiff preserves the relations, that is, for anyk-ary relation ρS of S and any k-tuple(s1, . . . , sk)ρS, we also have(f (s1), . . . , f (sk))ρR. Anisomorphismis a bijective homomorphism whose inverse is also a homomorphism. A

(4)

homomorphism fromRntoRis called apolymorphismofR. The set of polymorphisms ofRis called thecloneofRand is denoted by Clo(R). The set ofn-ary polymorphisms in Clo(R)is denoted by Clon(R). A unary polymorphism of a relational structure is called anendomorphism.Anautomorphismis a bijective endomorphism.

LetF be a set of operations on a setR. Ak-ary relationρis called aninvariant relation with respect toF if all the operations ofF are polymorphisms of the relational structure (R;ρ). In this case, we say that the operations inF preserve ρ. The set of all invariant relations with respect toF is denoted by Inv(F ). The set ofk-ary relations in Inv(F )is denoted by Invk(F ). We remark that Invk(F )is a lattice with respect to containment. For a relational structureR, Inv(Clo(R))is called therelational clone ofR.

In this paper, adirect productof ak-ary relationαand anl-ary relationβ is a relation obtained by permutation of coordinates from the relation

{(a1, . . . , ak, b1, . . . , bl)|(a1, . . . , ak)α, (b1, . . . , bl)β}.

We use the notationα×βto denote any of the direct products ofαandβ, from the context it will always be clear which of the direct products we think of.

A relationρ∈Invk(F )ismeet-irreducibleif it is not a proper meet of any two invariant relations of Invk(F ). Following the terminology in [6], we call a relationρ ∈ Invk(F )a critical relationwith respect toF if it is meet-irreducible in the lattice Invk(F )and is not a direct product of two relations with smaller arities. Let Crit(R)denote the set of the critical relations with respect to Clo(R). We call the elements of Crit(R)thecritical relations of R. The definition of Critk(R)is analogous.

Lemma 1 LetRbe a finite relational structure andρ∈Invk(Clo(R))a meet-irreducible relation. Thenρis a critical relation or a direct product of a critical relation and a finite power of the base set ofR.

Proof Suppose thatρis a meet-irreducible but not a critical relation. Thenρis of the form α×βfor suitable relationsα, β∈Inv(Clo(R)). Letαbe anl-ary andβanm-ary relation wherel+m=k. Thenρ=(Rl×β)×Rm). By meet irreducibility, eitherρ=Rl×β orρ = α×Rm. Without loss of generality, we assume thatρ = α×Rm. Now,αmust be meet-irreducible, for otherwise ρ would not be meet-irreducible. Thus, α is a meet- irreducible relation with a smaller arity thanρ. Hence, an induction on the arity ofρyields the claim.

Let 0R denote the equality relation of a setR. We say thatρ ∈ Invk(Clo(R))has a repetition of coordinatesif there exist two different coordinates such that by projectingρto these coordinates, the resulting binary relation is contained by 0R.

Lemma 2 LetRbe a finite relational structure andρ∈Invk(Clo(R))a meet-irreducible relation. Thenρhas no repetition of coordinates or it is of the formRk−2×0R. So every critical relation of arity at least three has no repetition of coordinates.

Proof If|R| =1, then the claim is trivial. Suppose that|R| ≥2 and the last two coordinates of the tuples inρare the same. Letαbe the projection ofρto the firstk−1 coordinates.

Thenρ =×R)(Rk−2×0R). Sinceρis meet irreducible andρ =α×R, we have thatρ=Rk−2×0R.

Later, we shall work in the class of posets. It is clear that this class is closed under finite power. Now, we are going to prove two theorems for classesK of general relational

(5)

structures such thatK is closed under finite power. These theorems play a fundamental role in the next section. First, we require a relativized version of a basic representation theorem for the invariant relations of a relational structure, cf. [4].

Theorem 3 LetK be a class of models in a fixed language of relational structures such thatK is closed under finite power. LetRbe a finite relational structure inK andρa non-emptyk-ary relation onR. Thenρ∈Invk(Clo(R))if and only if

ρ= {(h(s1), . . . , h(sk))|h:SR is a homomorphism} (1) for some finite relational structureSK and elementss1, . . . , skS.

Proof The sufficiency part is clear as a composition of homomorphisms is a homomor- phism itself. We prove the necessity part of the theorem. So letρ ∈Invk(Clo(R))and let n = |ρ|. The elements ofρas columns constitute ak×nmatrix, lets1, . . . , skRnbe the rows of this matrix in the natural order and letS =Rn. We note thatSK, since K is closed under finite power. To see that Eq.1holds observe that each homomorphism fromS toRis ann-ary operation in Clo(R)that preservesρ, henceρcontains the right hand side of Eq.1. By restricting then-ary projections—that are homomorphisms fromS toR— ontos1, . . . , sk, one sees that the converse containment also holds.

Ifρ, S ands1, . . . skSare as the ones in the statement of the preceding theorem, we say thatS definesρon s1, . . . , sk.

For setsH andP, the partial mapsf :H P are called thecolorings ofH withP. By acoloring of a relational structure, we naturally mean a coloring of its base set. We call the pair(S, f )anR-colored structureiff is a partial map fromS toR. AnR-colored structure(S, f )is calledextendibleif there exists a homomorphismg :SRwhich extends f. LetR andS be relational structures of the same type with base setsR and S, respectively. We say thatRcontainsS ifRSand each relation ofRcontains the corresponding relation ofS.

LetK be a class of models in a fixed language of relational structures such thatK is closed under finite power andRa finite relational structure inK. AnR-colored structure (S, f )is called anR-obstructionifS is a finite relational structure inK,(S, f )is not extendible, but for allSK properly contained inS,(S , f

S)is extendible.

The following theorem roughly says that to every critical relation we can assign an obstruction whose base relational structure defines it on the colored elements. A loose interpretation of this is that there are more obstructions than critical relations.

Theorem 4 LetK be a class of models in a fixed finite language of relational structures such that K is closed under finite power and R a finite relational structure in K. If ρ∈Critk(R)andρ= ∅,0R, then there exist a finite relational structureSK and an R-obstruction(S, f )withDom(f )= {s1, . . . , sk}such thatS definesρons1, . . . , sk. Proof We apply Theorem 3 as follows. We choose a finiteSK such thatS definesρ ons1, . . . , skSandS is minimal with respect to containment among the finite structures inK that defineρ. For every SK whereSS, letS denote the structure we get fromS by changingS toS ∪ {s1, . . . , sk}and retaining the relations ofS on S ∪ {s1, . . . , sk}.

Let

ρS = {(h(s1), . . . , h(sk))|h:S R is a homomorphism}.

(6)

It is obvious thatρS is an invariant relation ofRand that

ρρS . (2)

We claim that this inclusion is proper. If {s1, . . . , sk} ⊆ S, then the minimality ofS implies the proper inclusion. If{s1, . . . , sk} ⊆S, thenρS is obviously a direct product, so ρ=ρS , which together with Eq.2yields thatρρS indeed.

Letρ be the unique cover ofρ. Then, by using the proper inclusions we have just proved, we obtain that

ρρ

S ⊂S,S ∈K

ρS.

Letr=(r1, . . . , rk)ρ \ρ. We define the partial mapf onSbyf :siri, 1≤ik.

We have to argue thatfindeed is a map from its domain. By Lemma 2, it suffices to consider the case whenk=2 ands1 =s2. Sinceρ=0RandS definesρons1=s2,ρis a proper subset of 0R. Let(r, r) /ρ. Then the invariant relation generated byρ∪ {(r, r)}containsρ and, on the other hand, is a subset of the equality, hencer1=r2. Thus,fis a partial map.

We claim that(S, f ) is an R-obstruction. From r /ρ, we see that(S, f )is not extendible. Moreover, for anySS,SK, we haverρS and hence(S , f

S) is extendible.

The next theorem highlights the significance of critical relations. Let(Rn, f )be a finite R-colored structure andρak-ary invariant relation ofR. We say thatf preservesρif

for allr1, . . . , rk∈Dom(f ), (f (r1), . . . , f (rk))ρwhenever(r1, . . . , rk)ρ. (3) Theorem 5 Let(Rn, f )be a finiteR-colored structure. Thenf is extendible if and only if for allρ∈Critk(R),f preservesρ.

Proof The “only if” direction is obvious as critical relations are invariant. For the “if”

part, first, let us observe that property (3) is inherited for direct product and intersection of relations. Moreover, all invariant relations are obtained from critical relations with direct product and intersection. Sof preserves all invariant relations instead of critical relations.

This implies that if Dom(f ) = {a1, . . . , am}and(a1, . . . , am)is in an invariant relation αRm, then(f (a1), . . . , f (am))αas well. For the specific

α=

(h(a1), . . . h(am)) h:RnR is a homomorphism

, (4)

it is clear (taking the projections) that (a1, . . . , am) is in α, hence from our previous observation(f (a1), . . . , f (am))αas well. Then, by the definition in Eq.4, there is a homomorphism extendingf.

LetK be a class of models in a fixed finite language of relational structures such thatK is closed under finite power andRa finite relational structure inK. Notice that the set of R-obstructions depends on the classK, while the set of critical relations only depends on R. By Theorem 5, it suffices to know the critical relations ofRfor deciding the extendibil- ity of anR-colored structure(Rk, f ). On the other hand, the extendibility of(Rk, f )can be checked by the use of obstructions as well:(Rk, f )is extendible if and only if it contains noR-obstructions. By Theorem 4, in a way, there are less critical relations than obstruc- tions, and sometimes it is much easier to describe the critical relations in Crit(R)than the R-obstructions. So the extendibility of(Rk, f )might turn out to be easier to decide by the use of critical relations.

(7)

Fig. 3 Fences of small cardinality

In the next two sections, we supply a description of the critical relations of the crowns.

This is of significance since no tangible description is known for the obstructions of crowns within the class of posets. This is how we proceed: first we describe the binary critical relations of crowns and then we settle the general case. As an application, we prove that there is a polynomial-time algorithm that solves the subpower membership problem for any crown. Afenceis a one element poset or a length 1 poset whose comparability graph is a path, see Fig.3. LetFkdenote the(k+1)-element fence (whenkis even there are two such posets dual to each other, thenFkdenotes any of them), and letCkdenote the 2k-element crown.

3 The Binary Critical Relations ofCk

From now on, we work in the class of posets. All of the definitions and statements intro- duced in the preceding section are valid for posets as they constitute a class closed under finite power. In this section, we use Theorem 4 to describe the binary critical relations of Ck. We remark that the description of the binary critical relations ofCkcan also be obtained without Theorem 4, by using elementary facts about unary monotone operations ofCkand determining the smallest invariant relation containing a pair(a, b)Ck2.

Our starting point to obtain such a description is an earlier result in [12]. A ternary operation mis amajority operationif it satisfies the identities

m(x, y, y)=m(y, x, y)=m(y, y, x)=y.

Fig. 4 The lattice of binary invariant relations ofCk

...

D1 U1 U2 D2

Uk Dk

Ck2

0

Ck

D2UU2=D1 U1 U

o

(8)

It is a well known fact that the fences admit a majority operation, so by Proposition 3.1 in [12] we have the following.

Lemma 6 TheFk-obstructions are the non-extendibleFk-colored fences that are colored at the two endpoints.

Theorem 7 The Ck-obstructions with two colored elements are the non-extendible Ck- colored fences that are colored at the two endpoints.

Proof Let (H, f ) be a Ck-obstruction with two colored elements colored by a and b.

Clearly,aandbare different. LetF be a shortest path connectingaandbinCk. ThenF is a fence and(H, f )is a nonextendibleF-colored poset. So it contains anF-obstruction (H , f )such thatH is a fence whose endpoints are colored byaandb. By the preceding lemma,H has length shorter thanF, orH is the dual ofF. In both cases(H , f )is a non-extendibleCk-colored poset, sinceF is a shortest path connectingaandbinCk. By the minimality of(H, f ),(H, f )=(H , f )and we are done.

In a connected posetQ, for any two elementsa andb we define the updistance ofa frombto be the least positive integernsuch that there exists a sequence of elementsa = a0a1a2. . . an=binQ. The downdistance ofafrombis defined dually. We let

(a, b)and↓(a, b)denote the up and downdistance fromatob, respectively. We define some binary relations in the relational clone ofCk: let

Ul= {(a, b): ↑(a, b)l}andDl= {(a, b): ↓(a, b)l} wherelk.

Notice that the unary invariant relations of a finite posetPare∅andP, hence the only unary critical relation is∅. Therefore, the only direct product relations in Inv2(Clo(P))are

∅andP2.

Theorem 8 The binary critical relations ofCkareUlandDlwherelk.

Proof Notice that if a poset is not an antichain, then its equality relation is not critical since it is the intersection of≤and≤−1. So by Theorem 4 and Theorem 7, every binary critical relation ofCkis of the formUlorDlfor somelk. By the remark preceding the theorem, the only nonempty direct product relation in Inv2(Clo(Ck))isC2k and all of theUlandDl

are smaller thanCk2.

To conclude the proof, it suffices to verify that theUl andDl are meet-irreducible.

Observe that

Ul, DlUl+1, Dl+1

for alllk−1, andUlandDlare incomparable for alllk. Moreover Ul+1Dl+1=UlDl.

Notice that we have just described the lattice of binary invariant relations ofCk, see Fig.4.

Thus,UlandDlare meet-irreducible indeed for alllk.

4 Then-ary Critical Relations ofCkforn≥3

In this section we complete the characterization of the critical relations of crowns. Clearly, the automorphism group ofCk is isomorphic to the 2k-element dihedral group ifk ≥ 3,

(9)

and is isomorphic to the square of the two element group ifk=2. Observe that the range of any non-onto polymorphism ofCkis an at most(k+1)-element fence due to the fact that the largest down (up) distance is k inCk, and this property and connectedness are inherited for the powers ofCkand their monotone images. We call an endomorphismf of a poset aretractioniff2 = f. Aretractof a posetP is a poset that is isomorphic to the image of a retraction ofP. By coincidence, every at most(k+1)-element fence is a retract ofCk.

TheSłupecki relationSkon ak-element set wherek≥3 is the set of allk-tuples that have at mostk−1 pairwise different components. It is well known that a surjective operationf preservesSk if and only iff is essentially unary. So the clone of operations that preserve Sk consists of the unary operations and the non-surjective operations of thek-element set whenk≥3. This clone is called theSłupecki clone.

We require a result of Demetrovics and R´onyai which states that the clone of every crown is contained in the Słupecki clone, see Theorem 3.3 in [3]. An equivalent formulation of their theorem asserts that the surjective monotone operations of crowns are essentially unary. In the proof of Theorem 3.3 in [3], Demetrovics and R´onyai exhibited a poset that defines the Słupecki relation on suitable sequence of elements, proving in this way that the relational clone ofCkcontains the Słupecki relation. For completeness, here we give another proof of their theorem by the use of Jablonskiy’s lemma in [5].

Lemma 9(Jablonskiy, [5]) Fork≥3, letAbe ank-element set andf :AnAan onto operation that depends on at least two of its variables. Then there exist (k−1)-element subsetsA1, . . . , AnofAsuch thatf (A1× · · · ×An)=A.

Theorem 10(Demetrovics and R´onyai, [3]) In the clone ofCk, the onlyn-ary surjective operations are the ones of the formα(πi), whereαis an automorphism ofCkandπi is the projection to thei-th coordinate where1≤in.

Proof Suppose that f is an n-ary monotone onto operation of Ck that depends on at least two of its variables. We set A = Ck and apply Jablonskiy’s lemma. By leav- ing out an element from Ck we obtain a (2k − 1)-element fence. So the subposets A1, . . . ,Aninduced byA1, . . . , AninCk are(2k−1)-element fences. Notice that there is an element (the middle element) in these fences such that both the updistance and the downdistance from this special element to each element is at most k. This property is inherited for the productA1 × · · · ×An and, sincef is monotone andf (A1 × · · · × An) = Ck, it inherits for Ck. On the other hand, notice that in Ck there exists no element from which each element has updistance and downdistance at most k, a contra- diction. So the monotone onto operations ofCkare essentially unary, which concludes the proof.

Let AutCkdenote the automorphism group ofCk. We call a tuple a=(a1, . . . , an)Ckn

alarge range tupleif none of the(k+1)-element subfences ofCk contain{a1, . . . , an}. The tuples that are not of large range are calledsmall range tuples. For a large range tuple aCkn, we define the following relations:

Ra =Ckn\ {(σ (a1), . . . , σ (an)):σ∈AutCk}.

Lemma 11 For every large range tupleaCkn,Ra is a critical relation ofCk.

(10)

Proof First we prove that the relations in the claim are invariant relations of Ck. For a large range tuplea = (a1, . . . , an)Cknthe relation Ra has exactly 2kmissing tuples fromCnk, each of which can be mapped to the other by an automorphism ofCk. So to get a contradiction assume, thata = f (b, c, . . . )for some monotone operationf and tuples b, c, . . .Ra. However,fmust be surjective and, by the preceding theorem, we know that each surjective operation of a crown depends only on a single variable, so, say,a =σ (b) for some automorphismσofCk. This contradicts the fact thataRaandbRa.

Notice that for each large range tuplea = (a1, . . . , an)Ckn,Ra is a coatom in the lattice of then-ary invariant relations ofCk. Hence it is meet-irreducible. So by Lemma 1, Rais a critical relation or a direct product of a critical relation and a power ofCk. We argue that the latter possibility does not happen. Suppose that it does. ThenRa is of the form R×CklwhereRis an(nl)-ary relation. From the definition ofRa, sinceahas large range, it follows that|Ra| =(2k)n−2k. On the other hand, the projection of(σ (a1), . . . , σ (an)) onto the coordinates ofRis outside of Rfor allσ ∈ AutCk. This yields at leastk(2k)l elements outside ofRa, as every element ofCkis in ak-element orbit of AutCk. So|Ra| ≤ (2k)nk(2k)l, a contradiction. Thus, for any large range tupleaCkn,Ra is a critical relation ofCk.

We remark that it is also of interest to describe a poset that defines the relationRa on suitable sequence of elements for every large range tupleaCnk. This would yield an alternate proof of the preceding lemma, not using the Demetrovics-R´onyai result. We also note that the preceding lemma easily implies that the Słupecki relationS2kis in the relational clone ofCk, asS2kis the intersection of the 2k-ary relationsRa wherearuns through the 2k-tuples with pairwise different coordinates. The latter fact was proved by Demetrovics and R´onyai in [3], by exhibiting a poset that defines the Słupecki relation.

Forn≥2, a pair 1≤i, jnof distinct indices, and a binary relationS, we define the n-ary relation

Sij = {(a1, . . . , an)Cnk :(ai, aj)S}.

In later applications, the arity of the relationSijwill be clear from the context. Forn≥2, a pair 1≤i, jnof distinct indices, and ann-ary relationTletπij(T )denote the projection ofT to the coordinatesiandj. Finally, letTijdenote then-ary relation=ij(T ))ij. Theorem 12 LetLbe the set of large range tuples inCkn. For anyn-ary relationT in the relational clone ofCkwe have that

T =(a∈L\TRa)(1≤i<j≤nTij).

Proof Observe that the right-hand side is an intersection, and, clearly, all the meetands contain the left-hand side. Therefore all we need to prove is that for an arbitrary tupleb /T, there is a meetand of the right-hand side not containingb. For ab =a with large range, Ra suffices. Consequently, we only need to deal with a small rangeb. For a contradiction, let us suppose thatb /T is contained in all of the meetands of the right-hand side. In this case, we have tuplesbijT for all 1 ≤i < jnsuch thatπij(bij) = πij(b). Forb has a small range, it is contained in a(k+1)-element subfenceF ofCk. As we mentioned at the beginning of this section, there is a retractionr such thatr(Ck) = F. Applyingr to thebij componentwise, we obtain the tuplescij in T. Since for all 1 ≤ i < jn, πij(bij) = πij(cij), thecij interpolatebon every two coordinates. Letm be a majority operation ofF. By the Baker-Pixley argument in [1],bis generated from thecij, with the

(11)

help of the operationm(r(x), r(y), r(z)). Thus,cijT, 1≤i < jn, yieldsbT, a contradiction.

The following is a straightforward consequence of Theorem 8, Lemma 11 and the preceding theorem.

Corollary 13 The critical relations ofCkare the unaryrelation, the binary relationsUl

andDlfor alllk, and the relationsRafor all large range tuplesaCkn.

With little effort, we get the meet-irreducible elements in the lattice of then-ary invariant relations ofCk.

Corollary 14 The following is a complete list of the meet-irreducible elements in the lattice Invn(Clo(Ck)):

1. ∅,

2. SijwhereS=UlorS=Dlfor anyi=j, i, jnandlk, 3. Ra for all large range tuplesaCkn.

Proof By Theorem 12, every meet-irreducible element in Invn(Clo(Ck))is of the form as claimed. We only have to prove thatSij is meet-irreducible whereS = UlorS = Dl for lk, since the other type relations in the claim are critical by the preceding corollary, and hence they are meet-irreducible. LetCbe the intersection of all the relations that are of the form as in the claim and properly containSij. We shall prove thatC\Sij is non-empty.

First, observe that ifSijSpq, then{i, j} = {p, q}. By Theorem 8, there is pair(a, b)in the intersection of the binary invariant relations properly containingSsuch that(a, b) /S.

Letcbe ann-tuple whosei-th coordinate isaand whose other coordinates areb. Thencis a small range tuple, so it is contained inC\Sij.

5 The Subpower Membership Problem for Crowns

In this short section, we prove an easy but interesting corollary that immediately yields a polynomial-time algorithm to decide whether a partial mapf : CknCkis extendible. So SMP(Ck) is decidable in polynomial time for anyk. This can be proved by a direct use of Theorem 10, but here, we give a proof based on the description of the critical relations of Ck.

Letf :C Ck be a partial map with Dom(f)= {a1, . . . , al}. Thenf is calledlarge range if the tuple(f (a1), . . . , f (al))is of large range. We say thatf preserves the up (down) distanceif for anya, b∈Dom(f)

(f (a), f (b))≤↑(a, b) ((f (a), f (b))≤↓(a, b)).

Corollary 15 Letf :C Ck be a partial map. Thenf extends toC as a fully defined monotone map if and only if there is anisuch that

{(hi, f (h)):h=(h1, . . . , hn)∈Dom(f )} ⊆ {(c, σ (c)):cCk} (5) for someσAutCk, orfhas a small range and preserves the up and down distances.

Proof We know by Theorem 5 thatf is extendible if and only if it preserves all critical relations ofCk. We assume that Dom(f )is anl-element set.

(12)

First, suppose thatf has large range. Letf be thel-tuple determined by the values of f on a list of the elements of Dom(f ). Clearly,f is a large range tuple. By Lemma 11, the relationRf is a critical relation ofCk. Observe thatf preservesRf if and only if f is extendible. Indeed, iff preservesRf, then there must be anisuch that Eq.5holds for someσ∈AutCk, that is,f =σπi|Dom(f ), and soσπi is a monoton extension off to C. Thus, iffhas large range, thenf is extendible if and only if there is anisuch that Eq.5 holds for someσ ∈AutCk.

Let us suppose now thatf has small range. Then f vacuously preserves all critical relations of the formRafor all large range tuplesaC. Then, by Corollary 13,fextends toC if and only if f preserves the binary critical relations ofCk, which means that f preserves the up and down distances.

As for anya, bCknwherea=(a1, . . . , an)andb=(b1, . . . , bn)

(a, b)=max1≤i≤n(ai, bi)and ↓(a, b)=max1≤i≤n(ai, bi)

inC, all conditions of the corollary check in polynomial time. ThusSMP(Ck) is decidable in polynomial time for anyk. This implies thatRExt(Ck) is also decidable in polynomial time. On the other hand, as we mentioned in the introduction,Ext(Ck) isNP-complete.

Funding Open access funding provided by University of Szeged.

Data Availability Statement Data sharing not applicable to this article as no datasets were generated or analysed during the current study.

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder.

To view a copy of this licence, visithttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.

References

1. Baker, K., Pixley, F.F.: Polynomial interpolation and the Chinese Remainder Theorem for algebraic systems. Math. Z.143, 165–174 (1975)

2. Bulatov, A., Mayr, P., Szendrei, ´A.: The subpower membership problem for finite algebras with cube terms. Logical Methods in Computer Science15/1, 11:1–11:48 (2019)

3. Demetrovics, J., R´onyai, L.: Algebraic properties of crowns and fences. Order6(/1), 91–99 (1989) 4. Geiger, D.: Closed systems of functions and predicates. Pacific J. Math.27, 95–100 (1968)

5. Jablonskiy, S.V.: On functional completeness in the three-valued calculus (Russian). Dokl. Akad. Nauk.

SSSR95, 1153–1155 (1954)

6. Kearnes, K., Szendrei, ´A.: Clones of algebras with parallelogram terms. Internat. J. Algebra Comput.

22/1, 1250005 30 (2012)

7. Larose, B., Z´adori, L.: The complexity of the extendibility problem for finite posets. SIAM J. Discret.

Math.17(/1), 114–121 (2003)

8. McKenzie, R.: Monotone clones, residual smallness and congruence distributivity. Bull. Austral. Math.

Soc.41, 283–300 (1990)

9. Pratt, V., Tiuryn, J.: Satisfiability of inequalities in a poset. Fund Inform.28, 165–182 (1996) 10. Tardos, G.: A maximal clone of monotone operations which is not finitely generated. Order3/3, 211–218

(1986)

(13)

11. Willard, R.: Four Unsolved Problems in Congruence Permutable Varieties. Talk at the “Conference on Order, Algebra, and Logics”, Nashville (2007)

12. Z´adori, L.: Posets, near unanimity functions and zigzags. Bull. Aust. Math. Soc.47(/1), 79–93 (1993) 13. Z´adori, L.: Series-parallel posets with non-finitely generated clones. Order10/4, 305–316 (1993)

Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Ábra

Fig. 2 Poset T and some locked crowns of small cardinality
Fig. 4 The lattice of binary invariant relations of C k ...... D 1 U 1U2D2UkDkCk2 0 C kD2 U U 2 = D 1 U 1U o

Hivatkozások

KAPCSOLÓDÓ DOKUMENTUMOK

Using algorithms of computational commutative algebra we perform the study of the ideal generated by the coefficients of the period function of system (1.5) establishing that at

Therefore, the aim of this prospective, randomized, controlled, proof of concept (i.e.: testing it as a standalone extracorporeal treatment without the need of renal

Positive solutions for a Kirchhoff type problem with fast increasing weight and critical nonlinearity.. Xiaotao Qian B 1 and Wen

The idea is to consider a continuous path of functional starting from a symmetric functional and to prove a preservation result for min-max critical levels in order to obtain

This true load capacity exceeding that according to the theory of elasticity, the residual strain might be reckoned with in the practical design of structures.. In the

The load-carrying capacity of a sliding bearing ,vorking under conditions of boundary lubrication is charac- terized by critical values of operating variables (critical

kritikus minőségi tulajdonságok Critical Quality Attributes. kritikus folymat paraméterek Critical Process

5 ml⋅min -1 Feed rate has a critical influence on the formation of co­micronized particles Abbreviations: QTPPs, quality target product profiles; CQAs, critical quality