• Nem Talált Eredményt

B 1Introduction Robustutilitymaximisationinmarketswithtransactioncosts

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Ossza meg "B 1Introduction Robustutilitymaximisationinmarketswithtransactioncosts"

Copied!
20
0
0

Teljes szövegt

(1)

https://doi.org/10.1007/s00780-019-00389-0

Robust utility maximisation in markets with transaction costs

Huy N. Chau1·Miklós Rásonyi1

Received: 12 March 2018 / Accepted: 8 February 2019 / Published online: 23 April 2019

© The Author(s) 2019

Abstract We consider a continuous-time market with proportional transaction costs.

Under appropriate assumptions, we prove the existence of optimal strategies for in- vestors who maximise their worst-case utility over a class of possible models. We consider utility functions defined on either the positive axis or the whole real line.

Keywords Utility maximisation·Transaction cost·Model uncertainty Mathematics Subject Classification (2010) 91G10·49J27

JEL Classification G11

1 Introduction

In this paper, the existence of solutions to the utility maximisation problem from ter- minal utility is studied in the presence of model ambiguity. We assume that investors prepare for the worst-case scenario in the sense that they take the infimum of util- ity functionals over the class of possible models before maximising over admissible investment strategies.

The literature on robust optimisation typically assumes that uncertainty is mod- elled by a family of prior measuresP on some canonical space in which trajectories

Both authors were supported by the “Lendület” grant LP2015-6 of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences and by the NKFIH (National Research, Development and Innovation Office, Hungary) grant KH 126505.

B

H.N. Chau

chau@renyi.hu M. Rásonyi rasonyi@renyi.hu

1 Alfréd Rényi Institute of Mathematics, Hungarian Academy of Sciences, Reáltanoda utca 13-15, 1053 Budapest, Hungary

(2)

of the processes lie. Starting with Quenez [29] and Schied [34], the case in whichPis dominated by a reference measurePhas received ample treatment. In diffusion set- tings, this corresponds to uncertainty in the drift. Such an approach is not completely convincing since market participants may also be uncertain about the volatilities.

More recently, the non-dominated problem has also been studied in various con- texts. For instance, Tevzadze et al. [35] investigated a compact set of possible drift and volatility coefficients and tackled the robust problem by solving an associated Hamilton–Jacobi–Bellman equation. In Matoussi et al. [24], where volatility coeffi- cients are uncertain over a compact set and the drift is known, the theory of BSDEs is applied. Existence results in a fairly general class of models are available only in dis- crete time; see Nutz [27], Blanchard and Carassus [8], Neufeld and Šiki´c [26], Bartl [2], Bartl et al. [3] and Rásonyi and Meireles-Rodrigues [31]. A minimax result was established for bounded utilities in frictionless continuous-time markets in Denis and Kervarec [14].

As far as we know, our existence results below are the first to apply in a broad class of continuous-time models. We now summarise the principal ideas underlying our arguments. First, we work under proportional transaction costs. In this setting, strategies can be identified with finite-variation processes which we endow with a suitable convergence structure. Second, instead of a family of measures, we consider a parametrised family of stochastic processes on a fixed filtered probability space.

Necessarily, instead of one portfolio value, we need to consider a family of possible values corresponding to the respective parameters. Third, the latter fact forces us to take the family of strategies as our domain of optimisation (unlike most of the opti- mal investment literature since Kramkov and Schachermayer [21], which prefers to optimise over a set of random variables, the terminal values of possible portfolios).

Fourth, we exploit that the boundedness of terminal portfolio values in an appropri- ate sense implies boundedness of the strategies themselves (again, in an appropriate sense); this is false in continuous-time frictionless markets, but true in our setting.

Fifth, we profit from a method first developed in Rásonyi [30] that verifies the super- martingale property of a putative optimiser, based on a lemma of Delbaen and Owari [13]. Because of the fourth point above, our techniques do not seem to be applica- ble in the continuous-time frictionless setting. See, however, the companion paper by Rásonyi and Meireles-Rodrigues [31] which treats discrete-time frictionless markets.

The robust model in this paper, similarly to those introduced in Biagini and Pınar [6], Neufeld and Nutz [25], Lin and Riedel [22], assumes that there is a parametrisa- tion for the uncertain dynamics of risky assets. However, as we shall see below, no specific assumption is made about the parametrisation and an arbitrary index set is permitted. From a practical point of view, this approach is particularly tractable and easily implemented when it comes to calibration. For example, when estimating drift and volatility parameters for diffusion price processes, the results only give guesses (hopefully with some confidence sets) about the true values. Thus it is reasonable to parametrise ambiguity by considering suitable ranges which contain possible values for the coefficients being estimated.

From a mathematical point of view, the treatment of robust models in the present paper simplifies technical issues, as will become apparent from the proofs. Working on the same (filtered) probability space, instead of considering a family of measures,

(3)

gives us more flexibility by avoiding the canonical setting with problems concerning null events, filtration completion, etc. Measurable selection arguments, see Bouchard and Nutz [9], Biagini et al. [4] or Nutz [27], are not needed any more. Our approach can still incorporate most of the relevant model classes, and their laws on the path space do not need to be equivalent; see Sect.2.

Compactness plays an important role in proving the existence of optimisers. Usu- ally, the utility maximisation problem is transformed into an “abstract” version with random variables (the terminal wealth of admissible portfolios), and then convex compactness results inL0, in particular, Komlós-type arguments, are applied suc- cessfully; see Kramkov and Schachermayer [21]. Unfortunately, the robust setting is unlikely to be lifted to “abstract” versions, since the uncertainty produces a whole collection of wealth processes. As a result, Komlós-type arguments on the spaceL0 cannot be employed. Furthermore, the candidate dual problem in this setting does not, in general, admit a solution (see Bartl [2, Remark 2.3]) so that the usual approach of getting optimisers from solutions of dual problems seems inapplicable. Therefore, we are forced to work on the primal problem directly.

We are using two Komlós-type arguments. The first one is performed on the space of finite-variation processes (strategies), which gives a candidate for the optimiser, and the second is used in an Orlicz space context, to handle possible losses of trading when establishing the supermartingale property of the optimal wealth process, relying on Delbaen and Owari [13]. A crucial observation is that the utility of a portfolio is a sequentially upper semicontinuous function of the strategies (when the latter are equipped with a convenient convergence structure); see Guasoni [15] where the optimisation problem was viewed in a similar manner.

The paper is organised as follows. Section2introduces the robust market model and technical assumptions. Sections3and4study the existence of solutions for the robust utility maximisation problem when the utility functions are defined onR+ andR, respectively. Ramifications are discussed in Sect. 5. Some preliminaries on finite-variation processes and on Orlicz space theory are presented in Sect.5.

2 The market model

Let(Ω,F, (Ft)t∈[0,T], P )be a filtered probability space, where the filtration is as- sumed to be right-continuous andF0coincides with theP-completion of the trivial sigma-algebra. We define byL0the set of all a.s.-equivalence classes of random vari- ables and its positive cone byL0+.

LetΘbe a (non-empty) set, which is interpreted as the parametrisation of uncer- tainty. We consider a financial market consisting of a riskless assetSt0=1 for all t∈ [0, T]and a risky asset, whose dynamics is unknown. To describe the latter, we consider a family(Stθ)t∈[0,T],θΘ, of adapted, positive processes with continuous trajectories which represent the possible price evolutions. No condition is imposed onΘnor, for the moment, on the dynamics of the risky asset.

Remark 2.1 We now comment on the difference between our concept of model am- biguity and that of most previous papers, where a family of priors is considered on a canonical space.

(4)

Working on a given probability space and filtration amounts to fixing the infor- mation structure of the problem; the information flow is normally generated by a particular driving process (such as a multidimensional Brownian motion). Possible prices are then functionals of a parameter (finite- or infinite-dimensional, see Exam- ples2.2and2.4below) and the driving noise. Strategies are functionals adapted to the given information flow.

Considering a family of probabilities, one has greater liberty in the sense that no common driving noise is required, but the choice of strategies is limited; they must be adapted functionals on the canonical space, i.e., they are functions of the price process. In our modelling, the controls are adapted to an information flow that may be strictly bigger than the natural filtration of any possible price process.

In a strictly formal sense, none of two the approaches is more general than the other; see also examples in [31]. Intuitively, the standard setting is the more general one, while ours seems more easily tractable and fits better with a practical calibration and/or statistical inference framework.

We illustrate by the following examples that the present setting is useful and con- tains interesting models from previous studies.

Example 2.2 In the robust Black–Scholes market model, the risky asset satisfies the SDE

dSt(μ,σ )=St(μ,σ )(μ dt+σ dWt), S0(μ,σ )=s0>0,

whereμ,σ are constants andW is a standard Brownian motion. The uncertainty is modelled by

Θ= {θ=(μ, σ )∈R2:μμμ, σσσ},

whereμμ, 0< σσ are given constants. The classical Black–Scholes model corresponds to the case μ=μand σ =σ. It is observed that the laws of Sμ11, Sμ22 are singular when σ1=σ2. If only volatility uncertainty is considered, the family of laws is mutually singular. See [22,6] about treatments for similar models.

Remark 2.3 In the domain of robust finance, measurable selection techniques are of- ten used; see e.g. [27]. This requires a certain measurability of the family of laws corresponding to various models. In our present approach, however, this is not a necessity. Let e.g.Θbe a non-Borelian (or even non-analytic) subset of Θ in Ex- ample2.2above. Theorems3.6and4.7apply to the family of modelsSθ,θΘ, too.

Example 2.4 In the above example,Θwas a subset of a finite-dimensional Euclidean space. One may easily fabricate similar examples whereΘ is infinite-dimensional.

For instance, letΘconsist of all pairs of predictable processest, σt)such that for allt∈ [0, T],μt∈ [μ, μ]a.s. andσt∈ [σ , σ]a.s., and consider the SDEs

dSt(μ,σ )=St(μ,σ )tdt+σtdWt), S0(μ,σ )=s0>0, for each(μ, σ )Θ.

(5)

The following example extends the robust Black–Scholes model and allows an external economic factor.

Example 2.5 This is a factor model which is inspired by [20], but much simplified.

LetΘ⊆R2×2be a set. The risky asset is governed by the SDE dSθt =Stθ

m(Ytθ)+σ (θ11Ytθ+θ21)

dt+σ dWt1

, S0θ=s0>0, and the factor process evolves according to

dYtθ=

g(Ytθ)+ ρ, θ1·Ytθ+θ2·

dt+ρ1dWt1+ρ2dWt2, Y0θ=y0, wherem,g are suitable functions,W=(W1, W2)is a two-dimensional Brownian motion andρ=1, ρ2)∈R2a fixed parameter. The bracket·,· denotes the scalar product inR2. Note that the original setting of [20] cannot be directly transferred to the present one as it involves a family of weak solutions of SDEs which are not necessarily realisable on our given stochastic basis.

The risky asset is traded under proportional transaction costsλ(0,1). More pre- cisely, investors have to pay a higher (ask) priceSθ when buying the risky asset, but receive a lower (bid) price(1λ)Sθ when selling it.

LetV denote the family of nondecreasing, right-continuous functions on[0, T] which are 0 at time 0. Let V denote the set of tripletsH =(H, H, H0), where Ht,Ht,t∈ [0, T], are optional processes such thatH(ω), H(ω)V for each ωΩ andH0∈R(deterministic). The space V can be equipped with a convergence structure; see Sect.A.1below for details.

Each trading strategy corresponds to an elementHV. In this formulation,H denotes the cumulative amount of transfers from the riskless asset to the risky one andHrepresents the transfers in the opposite direction;H0encodes the amount of initial transfer from the riskless asset to the risky one. Therefore the portfolio position in the risky asset at timet equalsφt:=H0+HtHt,t∈ [0, T],φ0:=0.

For any x∈R, we denote x+:=max{0, x}, x:=max{0,−x}. For an initial capitalx∈R, the dynamics of the cash account of an investor following the strategy Hevolves according to

Wtx(θ, H ):=xH0+S0θ+H0S0θ(1λ)t

0

SuθdHu+ t

0

(1λ)SθudHu, fort∈ [0, T]. The liquidation value is defined by

Wtx,liq(θ, H ):=Wtx(θ, H )+φ+t (1λ)StθφtSθt. (2.1) We introduce the definition of consistent price systems, which play a similar role to martingale measures in frictionless markets; see [19,17,16].

Definition 2.6 For eachθΘ, aλ-consistent price system (λ-CPS) for the modelθ is a pair(S˜θ, Qθ)of a probability measureQθP and a (càdlàg)Qθ-local martin-

(6)

galeS˜θ such that

(1λ)Stθ≤ ˜StθStθ a.s., for eacht∈ [0, T]. (2.2) Aλ-strictly consistent price system (λ-SCPS) is a CPS such that the inequalities in (2.2) are strict.

We impose the existence of consistent price systems for every modelSθ. In Sect.3, we need the following assumption in order to be able to use the results of [12].

Assumption 2.7 For eachθΘ and for all 0< μ < λ, the price processSθ admits aμ-CPS.

This assumption is fulfilled if for every θΘ, the process Sθ satisfies the no- arbitrage condition forμ-transaction cost for allμ >0; see [17]. See Example4.6 for a risky asset violating Assumption2.7.

Clearly, if 0< μ < λ, then aμ-CPS is also aλ-SCPS.

Lemma 2.8 If(S˜θ, Qθ)is aλ-strictly consistent price system, the random variable δ(θ ):= inf

t∈[0,T]min{ ˜Stθ(1λ)Stθ, Stθ− ˜Stθ} (2.3) is almost surely strictly positive andEQθ[δ(θ )]<∞.

Proof The argument follows that of [19, Lemma 3.6.4].

Let

Mθ:= {dQθ/dP : (S˜θ, Qθ)is aλ-CPS}. For a consistent price system(S˜θ, Qθ), we define the process

Vtx(θ, H ):=Wtx(θ, H )+φtS˜tθ,

without emphasising the dependence ofV on the specific consistent price system. It is easy to check thatWtx,liq(H )Vtx(θ, H )a.s., for eacht∈ [0, T].

3 Utility function onR+

Assumption 3.1 The utility functionU:(0,)→Ris nondecreasing and concave.

Define the convex conjugate ofUby V (y):=sup

x>0

U (x)xy

, y >0.

Admissible strategies are defined in a natural way, thanks to the domain of the utility function.

(7)

Definition 3.2 A strategy H=(H, H, H0)V is admissible for initial capital x >0 and for the modelθΘif for eacht∈ [0, T],

Wtx,liq(θ, H )≥0 a.s.

Denote byAθ(x)the set of all admissible strategies forθ. Set Aθ0(x):= {H∈Aθ(x): φT =H0+HTHT=0}

andA(x)=

θΘAθ0(x).

Remark 3.3 For eachHA(x)andθΘ,

WTx,liq(θ, H )=WTx(θ, H )=VTx(θ, H )

due toφT =0. We also see from (2.1) that at time 0< t < T, the liquidation value is neither concave nor convex inH. However, the conditionφT =0 recovers concav- ity of the liquidation value with respect toH at time T. This is crucial for finding maximisers in the subsequent analysis.

Letx >0. Note thatA(x)= ∅since it contains the identically zero strategy. Our investors want to find the optimiser for

u(x):= sup

H∈A(x) θinfΘE

U

WTx,liq(θ, H ) . (3.1)

It is worth noting that maximising inHis a concave problem; however, minimising overΘis not a convex problem.

For eachθΘandx >0, we denote

Cθ(x):= {XL0+: XWTx,liq(θ, H )for someHAθ(x)}.

For eachy >0, the set of supermartingale deflatorsBθ(y)consists of the strictly positive processesY =(Yt0, Yt1)t∈[0,T],Y00=y, such thatY1/Y0∈ [(1λ)Sθ, Sθ] andWx(θ, H )Y0+φY1is a (càdlàg) supermartingale for allHAθ(x). Also, we define

Dθ(y):= {YT0:(Y0, Y1)Bθ(y)}. The primal and dual value functions for theθ-model are

uθ(x):= sup

f∈Cθ(x)

E[U (f )], vθ(y):= inf

h∈Dθ(y)

E[V (h)].

The next lemma states that the setsCθ(x)andDθ(y)are polar to each other. It follows directly from [12, Proposition 2.9].

Lemma 3.4 Fixx, y >0. Let Assumption2.7be in force. A random variableXL0+ satisfiesXCθ(x)if and only ifE[XY] ≤xyfor allYDθ(y). A random variable YL0+satisfiesYD(y)if and only ifE[XY] ≤xyfor allXCθ(x).

(8)

We impose a technical assumption.

Assumption 3.5 The dual value functionvθ(y), y >0, is finite for allθΘ.

Theorem 3.6 Letx >0. Under Assumptions2.7,3.1,3.5, the robust utility maximi- sation problem (3.1) admits a solution, i.e., there isHA(x)satisfying

u(x)= inf

θΘE U

WTx,liq(θ, H) .

WhenUis bounded from above, the same conclusion holds assuming only that there exists (at least) oneθ˜∈Θfor which there exists aλ-SCPS.

Proof IfUis constant, there is nothing to prove. Otherwise, by adding a constant to U, we may assume thatU () >0>limx0U (x).

Notice thatU () >0 and

uθ(x)U (x) (3.2)

imply lim infx→∞uθ(x)/x≥0. From Lemma3.4, trivially,

uθ(x)vθ(y)+xy (3.3)

for ally >0. Fixingy, we obtain lim supx→∞uθ(x)/xy, and sending y to zero gives

xlim→∞

uθ(x)

x =0. (3.4)

After these preparations, we turn to the main arguments. Assumption3.5, (3.3) and (3.2) imply thatuθ(x)is finite for eachθand so isu(x). LetHnA(x),n∈N, be a maximising sequence, i.e.,

θinfΘE U

WTx,liq(θ, Hn)u(x) asn→ ∞.

Let us fix for the momentθΘand aμ-CPS(S˜θ, Qθ)with 0< μ < λ. First, we prove that the process

Vtx(θ, Hn)=Wtx(θ, Hn)+φtnS˜tθ is aQθ-supermartingale for alln. Indeed, Itô’s formula gives

dVtx(θ, Hn)= −StθdHtn,+(1λ)StθdHtn,+ ˜Stθtn+φtndS˜tθ

=(S˜tθStθ) dHtn,+

(1λ)Stθ− ˜Stθ

dHtn,+φtndS˜tθ. Admissibility ofHnimplies

(9)

(H0n)+(Sθ0− ˜S0θ)+ t

0

(Suθ− ˜Suθ) dHun,+ t

0

S˜uθ(1λ)Suθ dHun,

+ t

0

φundS˜uθ

x+(H0n)

S0θ(1λ)− ˜S0θ +

t 0

φnudS˜uθ +

. (3.5)

In particular, we obtain t

0

φundS˜uθ

x+(H0n)S0θ(1λ) (3.6)

for every t ∈ [0, T], and therefore t

0φundS˜uθ, t ∈ [0, T], is a Qθ-supermar- tingale; see [1, Corollary 3.5]. It follows that Vtx(θ, Hn), t ∈ [0, T], is also a Qθ-supermartingale.

We claim that supn(H0n)is finite. If this were not the case, then along a subse- quencenk,k∈N, we should have(H0nk)→ ∞,k→ ∞, and(H0nk)+=0,k∈N. TakingQθ-expectations in (3.5), we should get

0≤x+ lim

k→∞(H0nk)

S0θ(1λ)− ˜S0θ

= −∞,

a contradiction. Hence the supremum is indeed finite.

Furthermore, from the supermartingale property of t

0φundS˜θu,t ∈ [0, T], and from (3.6),

sup

n

EQθ

T 0

φundS˜θu +

x+sup

n

(H0n)Sθ0(1λ) follows. Using (2.3), we deduce from (3.5) that

sup

n

EQθ

(H0n)+δ(θ )+ T

0

δ(θ )

dHun,+dHun,

≤sup

n

EQθ

(H0n)+(S0θ− ˜S0θ)+ T

0

(Suθ− ˜Suθ) dHun,+S˜uθ(1λ)Suθ dHun,

<.

Apply Lemma A.1 with the choice dQ/dQθ :=δ(θ )/EQθ[δ(θ )]. It implies that there exist convex weightsαjn≥0,j =n, . . . , M(n), withM(n)

j=n αjn=1 such that H˜n:=M(n)

j=n HnHin V. Since the utility function is concave, we obtain that H˜n,n∈N, is also a maximising sequence as

θinfΘE U

WTx,liq(θ,H˜n) ≥ inf

θΘE U

WTx,liq(θ, Hn) −→u(x) asn→ ∞.

(10)

We now prove that the sequenceU+(WTx,liq(θ,H˜n)),n∈N, is uniformly inte- grable for eachθΘ. Suppose by contradiction that the sequence is not uniformly integrable for someθ. Then one can find disjoint setsAnF,n∈N, and a constant α >0 such that

E U+

WTx,liq(θ,H˜n)

1Anα forn≥1.

Setwn=n

i=1WTx,liq(θ,H˜i)1{

WTx,liq(θ,H˜i)u0}1Ai, where u0 is chosen such that it satisfiesU (u0)=0. It is immediate that

E[U (wn)] = n

i=1

E U+

WTx,liq(θ,H˜i)

1Ainα.

In addition, for any hDθ(1), the supermartingale property shows that E[hwn] ≤nx. Consequently, we obtainwnCθ(nx)by Lemma3.4. We compute

uθ(nx)

nxE[U (wn)]

nxα x >0,

and passing to the limit whenn→ ∞contradicts (3.4). ThusU+(WTx,liq(θ,H˜n)), n∈N, is indeed uniformly integrable.

Since H˜nH in V, WTx,liq(θ,H˜n)WTx,liq(θ, H) almost surely by Re- markA.2. So Fatou’s lemma and uniform integrability imply

lim sup

n→∞

θinfΘE U

WTx,liq(θ,H˜n) ≤ inf

θΘlim sup

n→∞ E U

WTx,liq(θ,H˜n)

≤ inf

θΘE U

WTx,liq(θ, H) ,

which proves thatHis an optimiser. It remains to check thatHA(x). For each θ,Wtx,liq(θ, H)≥0 a.s., for Lebesgue-almost everyt, by RemarkA.2; so we get admissibility ofHsincetWtx,liqis a.s. right-continuous.

In the case whereU is bounded from above, it is enough to perform the first part of the above argument forθ, obtain˜ H and then simply invoke Fatou’s lemma to

complete the proof.

Remark 3.7 In the classical theory where there is no uncertainty, i.e., whenΘcon- tains only one element, the existence result holds assuming the finiteness ofu(x)only.

This condition, however, does not suffice to find optimisers in the robust problem. In- deed, the finiteness ofu(x)makes the robust problem well posed, compactness gives a candidate for the optimiser, but this is still not enough to prove that the candidate is indeed an optimiser. To complete the proof, it is necessary to have upper semiconti- nuity of the expected utility when considered as a function of the strategy variable. In [27], a counterexample (in whichu(x)is finite, but one could not find an optimiser) is given in the nondominated case. The author’s argument exploits precisely the lack of upper semicontinuity property in one model. Furthermore, [27] gives a sufficient

(11)

condition to have upper semicontinuity, namely the integrability of the positive part of the utility function under every possible model; see [27, Theorem 2.2] and also [8] for further developments. In our approach, upper semicontinuity follows from the finiteness of the dual value function for every model.

4 Utility functions onR

Assumption 4.1 The utility function U:R→R is bounded from above, nonde- creasing, concave andU (0)=0. Define the convex conjugate ofUby

V (y):=sup

x∈R

U (x)xy

, y >0.

We also assume that

x→−∞lim U (x)

x = ∞, (4.1)

lim sup

y→∞

V (2y)

V (y) <. (4.2)

Remark 4.2 Under (4.1), the functionV takes finite values andV (y) >0 forylarge enough; hence (4.2) makes sense. The conditionU (0)=0 is used only to simplify calculations. Condition (4.1) is mild and so is (4.2); indeed, as shown in [32, Corol- lary 4.2(i)], for every utility functionUwith reasonable asymptotic elasticity, its con- jugateV satisfies (4.2). The studies [11,23] assumed a smoothU which is strictly concave on its entire domain; we need neither smoothness nor strict concavity ofU.

As discussed in [7,33], the choice of admissible trading strategies is a delicate issue in the context of utility maximisation with utility functions defined on the real line.

A common approach is to consider strategies whose wealth processes are bounded uniformly from below by a constant. This choice, however, turns out to be restrictive and fails to contain optimisers. In frictionless markets, [33] proved that for a utility function having reasonable asymptotic elasticity, the optimal investment process is a supermartingale under each martingale measureQsuch thatE[V (dQ/dP )]is finite.

We thus use the supermartingale property to define admissibility, just like in [28,10].

To begin with, we define

MθV= {Qθ:(S˜θ, Qθ)is aλ-consistent price system,E[V (dQθ/dP )]<∞}, the set of local martingale measures in consistent price systems for theθ-model with finite generalised relative entropy.

Definition 4.3 We define

Aθ(x):= {HV:φT =0, Vx(θ, H )is aQθ-supermartingale

for eachλ-consistent price system(S˜θ, Qθ)withQθMθV} and setA(x):=

θΘAθ(x).

(12)

The optimisation problem becomes u(x)= sup

H∈A(x) θinfΘE

U

WTx,liq(θ, H ) .

Assumption 4.4 For eachθΘ, the price processSθ admits aλ-SCPS(Qθ,S˜θ) such thatQθMθV.

Remark 4.5 Unlike in [11,12,23] and in Sect.3, we do not impose in the present section the existence of consistent price systems for every transaction cost coefficient 0< μ < λ; we only stipulate Assumption4.4. The following example shows that it is quite possible to have CPSs for relatively largeλwithout having them for arbitrarily smallμ. In this example, there is an obvious arbitrage, in the language of [17], which persists (ceases) with sufficiently small (large) transaction costs.

Example 4.6 Let us consider St=1+t+ 1

2πarctanWt, t∈ [0,1].

Ifλ <3/7, then(1λ)S1>1=S0a.s.; therefore, there is no consistent price system.

Ifλ≥2/3, then

St(1λ)≤3/4≤St, t∈ [0, T]. In other words,(P ,S˜≡3/4)is a consistent price system.

Theorem 4.7 Under Assumptions4.1 and 4.4, there exists a strategy HA(x) such that

u(x)= inf

θΘE U

WTx,liq(θ, H) .

Proof We adapt certain techniques of [30]. Our arguments bring novelties even in the case where Θ is a singleton (i.e., without model uncertainty). Define Φ(x)= −U (x)forx≥0. Its conjugate (in the sense of Sect.A.2below) is

Φ(y):=

0, if 0≤yβ,

V (y)V (β), ify > β,

whereβis the left derivative ofUat 0; see [5]. Note thatΦ,Φare Young functions andΦ is of class2by (4.2).

LetHnA(x),n∈N, be a maximising sequence, i.e.,

θinfΘE U

WTx,liq(θ, Hn)u(x)U (x). (4.3) First, for allθΘ, it holds that

sup

n

E U

WTx,liq(θ, Hn) <. (4.4)

(13)

Indeed, let us assume that there existsθΘsuch that (4.4) does not hold, or equiv- alently, there exists a subsequencenk=nθk,k∈N, such that

E U

WTx,liq(θ, Hnk) > k.

Let us denote byCan upper bound ofU; then E

U

WTx,liq(θ, Hnk)CE U

WTx,liq(θ, Hnk) −→ −∞ ask→ ∞ which contradicts (4.3). Hence (4.4) indeed holds.

Consider aλ-strictly consistent price system(S˜θ, Qθ). Fenchel’s inequality gives U

VTx(θ, Hn)

V (dQθ/dP )(dQθ/dP )VTx(θ, Hn) and therefore

(dQθ/dP )

VTx(θ, Hn)

U

VTx(θ, Hn)

V (dQθ/dP )

. (4.5) From (4.4) and (4.5), we deduce that

sup

n

EQθ

VTx(θ, Hn)

<. (4.6)

Itô’s formula gives

dVtx(θ, Hn)= −StθdHtn,+(1λ)StθdHtn,+ ˜Stθtn+φtndS˜tθ

=(S˜tθStθ) dHtn,+

(1λ)Stθ− ˜Stθ

dHtn,+φtndS˜tθ. This implies that

(H0n)+(S0θ− ˜S0θ)+ t

0

(Suθ− ˜Suθ) dHun,↑+ t

0

S˜uθ(1λ)Suθ dHun,↓

+ t

0

φundS˜uθ

x+(H0n)

S0θ(1λ)− ˜S0θ +

Vtx(θ, Hn) +

t

0

φundS˜uθ +

.

In particular, t

0

φundS˜uθ

x+(H0n)S0θ(1λ)+

Vtx(θ, Hn)

. (4.7)

For each n, the process Vx(θ, Hn) is a Qθ-supermartingale; so there exists a Qθ-martingale which dominates the right-hand side of (4.7) and also the left-hand side of the same expression. [1, Corollary 3.5] implies thatt

0φundS˜uθ,t∈ [0, T], is

(14)

aQθ-supermartingale. We get supn(H0n)<∞in the same way as in the proof of Theorem3.6. Consequently, (4.6), (4.7) and the boundedness of(H0n),n∈N, give

sup

n

EQθ

T 0

φtndS˜θt +

<.

Noting that(S˜θ, Qθ)is aλ-strictly consistent price system, we obtain from the above arguments that

sup

n

EQθ

(H0n)+δ(θ )+δ(θ ) T

0

(dHtn,+dHtn,)

≤sup

n

EQθ

(H0n)+(S0θ− ˜S0θ)+ T

0

(Stθ− ˜Stθ) dHtn,+S˜tθ(1λ)Stθ dHtn,

<∞.

LemmaA.1implies the existence of convex weightsαjn≥0,j=n, . . . , M(n), with M(n)

j=n αnj=1 such thatH˜n:=M(n)

j=n αnjHnHin V. Since the utility function is concave,H˜n,n∈N, is also a maximising sequence.

We now prove that HA(x); in other words, the process Vx(θ, H) is a Qθ-supermartingale, for eachQθMθV and eachθΘ. To do so, it suffices to con- trol the negative part ofVx(θ, H). It should be emphasised that (4.6) is not enough for our purposes and a stronger statement using Orlicz space theory is needed (see Sect.A.2). Using concavity ofUand linearity ofVx(θ,·), we get from (4.4) that

sup

n

E U

VTx(θ,H˜n) <∞. (4.8) Applying LemmaA.3 to the sequence of random variables in (4.8), we obtain convex weightsαjn≥0,njM(n), withM(n)

j=n αjn=1 such that Zn:=

M(n)

j=n

αjn

VTx(θ,H˜n)

satisfy

L:=sup

n

Zn

Φ<. (4.9)

By the Fenchel inequality and (4.9), EQθ

sup

n

Zn

=LEQθ

supnZn L

LE

Φ dQθ

dP

+LE

Φ

supnZn L

<∞ (4.10)

(15)

for eachQθMθV. WhenL=0, we have thatEQθ[supnZn] =0 trivially. Now we define

Hn:=

M(n)

j=n

αjnH˜n,

which is also a maximising sequence. Using the fact that the negative part of a su- permartingale is a submartingale, we getVtx(θ, Hn)EQθ[VTx(θ, Hn)|Ft]and thus

sup

n

Vtx(θ, Hn)≤sup

n

EQθ[VTx(θ, Hn)|Ft]. Taking expectations on both sides of the above inequality, we obtain

EQθ

sup

n

Vtx(θ, Hn)

EQθ

sup

n

EQθ[VTx(θ, Hn)|Ft]

EQθ

EQθ sup

n

VTx(θ, Hn)Ft

=EQθ

sup

n

VTx(θ, Hn)

EQθ

sup

n

Zn

<,

using (4.10). Since the random variable supn(Vtx(θ, Hn))is an upper bound of the sequenceVtx(θ, Hn),n∈N, this proves uniform integrability of that sequence un- derQθ at any timet∈ [0, T].

Clearly,HnH in V and therefore Vtx(θ, Hn)Vtx(θ, H) a.s., for every t∈ [0, T] \ZwhereZhas Lebesgue measure 0; see RemarkA.2. Also,

Vtx(θ, H)

EQθ

sup

n

VTx(θ, Hn)Ft

, t∈ [0, T], (4.11) where the latter process is a martingale, and hence(Vtx(θ, H))t∈[0,T]is uniformly integrable. Let 0≤st < T be both in[0, T] \Z. Noting the supermartingale prop- erty, Fatou’s lemma yields

EQθ[Vtx(θ, H)|Fs] =EQθ

lim inf

n→∞ Vtx(θ, Hn)Fs

≤lim inf

n→∞ EQθ[Vtx(θ, Hn)|Fs]

≤lim inf

n→∞ Vsx(θ, Hn)=Vsx(θ, H).

The same argument works fort=T, too. Now it extends to arbitraryt∈ [0, T]by using Fatou’s lemma and (4.11). Finally, it extends to arbitrarys∈ [0, T]by the back- ward martingale convergence theorem and by right-continuity ofsVsx(θ, H).

This means thatVx(θ, H)is aQθ-supermartingale and thereforeHA(x).

Hivatkozások

KAPCSOLÓDÓ DOKUMENTUMOK

A space–time fractional diffusion-wave equation is obtained from the classical diffusion or wave equation by replacing the first or second order time derivatives and second order

BURKE’s theory of identity control (Burke, a) and using a metaphor of space I formulate the hypothesis that the solution to the fundamental question of economic ethics lies one

Our main result is that, for sufficiently small reaction lag r, the automatic control described by system (1.1) and (1.2) is perfect: the zero solution is globally

Keywords: folk music recordings, instrumental folk music, folklore collection, phonograph, Béla Bartók, Zoltán Kodály, László Lajtha, Gyula Ortutay, the Budapest School of

The aim of this article is to discuss the manner in which the Late Iron Age communities from Transylvania organized the space and manipulated the landscape, on one hand, and

In this paper we presented our tool called 4D Ariadne, which is a static debugger based on static analysis and data dependen- cies of Object Oriented programs written in

This method of scoring disease intensity is most useful and reliable in dealing with: (a) diseases in which the entire plant is killed, with few plants exhibiting partial loss, as

The most important medieval Jewish visionary author before Dante was Abraham ibn Ezra, who lived in the first half of the twelfth century and spent some time of his life in Italy, at