• Nem Talált Eredményt

How is innovation policy informed: Utilitarianism versus the capability approach

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Ossza meg "How is innovation policy informed: Utilitarianism versus the capability approach"

Copied!
19
0
0

Teljes szövegt

(1)

HOW IS INNOVATION POLICY INFORMED: UTILITARIANISM VERSUS THE CAPABILITY APPROACH

Zoltán Bajmócy – Judit Gébert

Innovation policy strives for fulfilling objectives that are formulated in the political arena: growth in economic performance, in productivity, or in employment. While the examination of these aims’ adequacy is beyond the scope of innovation studies, they are increasingly questioned in other fields. Present paper builds on one of the most influencing criticisms of the dominating growth-centred utilitarian tradition of economics: Amartya Sen’s capability approach. We put forth the question that: what set of information would be required for the design and evaluation of innovation policy, if we relied on the capability approach, and how would this informational basis differ from that of the growth centred view. We conclude that switching to the capability approach would result in a sea-change, but the systems of innovation approach, as a methodology, would still be of good use.

Keywords: informing innovation policy, welfare economics, utilitarianism, capability approach EAEPE research area: [D] Innovation and technological change

1. Introduction

There has once been a long-lasting debate in the literature regarding the welfare roots of innovation policies. This debate resulted in the spread of policies that are based on evolutionary arguments, and inferred the emergence of the systems of innovation approach (Metcalfe 1994, 1995). Nowadays system failures are considered to be the underlying rationales for innovation policies instead of market failures.

According to Edquist (2002) two conditions must be fulfilled for there to be reason for public intervention in a market economy. First, capitalist actors must fail to achieve the objectives formulated (a problem must exist). Second, the state must have the ability to

Zoltán Bajmócy, associate professor. University of Szeged, Faculty of Economics and Business Administration.

E-mail: bajmocyz@eco.u-szeged.hu

Judit Gébert, PhD student. University of Szeged, Faculty of Economics and Business Administration. E-mail:

gebert.judit@eco.u-szeged.hu

Present paper was supported by the János Bolyai Reasearch Scholarship of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences.

The publication is supported by the European Union and co-funded by the European Social Fund. Project title:

“Broadening the knowledge base and supporting the long term professional sustainability of the Research University Centre of Excellence at the University of Szeged by ensuring the rising generation of excellent scientists.” Project number: TÁMOP-4.2.2/B-10/1-2010-0012

(2)

mitigate the problem. Edquist provides clarification on the term “objective” only in a footnote, still it is one of the most explicit descriptions on the axioms of innovation policy:

I assume that objectives – whatever they are – are already determined in a political process. … With regard to innovation policy the most common objectives are formulated in terms of economic growth, productivity growth, or employment” (Edquist, 2002, p. 220.).

Therefore, innovation policy places its welfare assumptions beyond its scope. It does not examine whether the formulated objectives contribute to welfare gain on the whole, or not. It is rather interested in the most adequate ways to meet the – a priori given – objectives.

However, these objectives are being increasingly questioned. The benevolence of growth seems to be unambiguous in the utilitarian traditions of economics. But it is not apparent in one of the most influential criticisms of utilitarianism: the capability approach (CA) of the Nobel-laureate Amartya Sen. In his view the relation of wealth and well-being is neither exclusive (since there are significant influences on our well-being other than wealth), nor uniform (since the impact of wealth depends on many factors) (Sen 1999, p. 14.).

Although this debate is beyond the scope of innovation policy, its consequences may affect its gist. Present paper does not intend to participate in the “utilitarianism versus capability approach” debate. It is rather interested in the question, that what would be the consequences, if we relied on the capability approach instead of the growth centred utilitarian view. How would the basis of policy differ in the two approaches?

Therefore we focus on the informational basis of innovation policy: the set of information that is used and the set of information that is excluded during the design and the evaluation of policies (Sen 1999). Today’s innovation policies endeavour to refine the operation of the innovation system: the set of factors that influence the generation, the diffusion and the utilization of technologies that have economic value (Lundvall 1992, Nelson – Rosenberg 1993). In other words: innovation systems are considered to be effective if they are able to speed up technological change, and ultimately to contribute to economic growth.

Therefore, the informational basis of innovation policy embraces elements and functions that may contribute to, or hinder the speeding up of technological change. What is no less important, they exclude all the information that seems to be unnecessary from this perspective. We argue however, that many aspects of technological change that are redundant, or can be easily reduced to a common denominator in the utilitarian approach, seem to be

(3)

relevant and much more complex in the capability approach. Evaluation of policies may significantly differ within the two approaches.

The paper first provides a brief introduction into the capability approach in section 2.

Then it outlines the informational basis of an innovation policy that is based on the arguments of the CA in section 3. In section 4. we analyse how this new informational basis differs from that of the growth-centred utilitarian approach. Section 5. sketches the outlines of innovation policies in CA. We draw conclusions in section 6.

2. The capability approach

Capability approach was developed by the Nobel laureate Amartya Sen, and his works were followed by several capability theorists, researchers and policy designers. Sen's ideas significantly contribute to the contemporary discourses about well-being, development, poverty reduction and many other areas of social sciences.

Most generally the approach is applied to assess well-being of countries or societies. It is a framework or evaluative space, which shows what set of information should be looked at, if we want to assess how well a life is going. Thus, the approach is capable of not just evaluating aggregate well-being of a community but also of making interpersonal comparisons of well-being (Robeyns 2006, Alkire et al. 2008).

In economics – or welfare economics – the capability approach is brought into play to evaluate the level of development or the quality of life; to identify the poor in developing countries, or to assess complex aspects of well-being in advanced economies, inter alia. In political science, it is used to debate policies, or to assess development projects (Alkire 2002).

It is important to emphasize that the capability approach is very much open-ended, and is more an evaluative framework than a theory with exact definitions (Gasper 2007). Hence, to make use of the approach, the theory needs to be extended according to the aim of the actual research topic. This aspect of the approach leaves huge space for different interpretations and extensions (Robeyns 2006).

The capability approach arose very much from the dissatisfaction with the classical frameworks and tools of welfare theories (Sen 1999, 2005). It argues that utilitarian welfare theories, subjective well-being measures, and evaluations about primary goods or basic needs have many disadvantages and are built on a too narrow “informational basis” to be able to assess such a multidimensional phenomenon like well-being (Sen 1999).

(4)

Inserting additional information into the previous concepts of well-being was not a new idea when Sen molded the capability approach. An enormous stream of works had already existed on social indicators, on the quality of life and subjective well-being indicators. Sen’s important contribution is conceptualizing, helping to focus, and organizing these efforts (Gasper 2007).

A useful way to explain the capability approach might start with defining two of its fundamental concepts: functioning and capability. “Functionings represent parts of the state of a person – in particular the various things that he or she manages to do or be in leading a life” (Sen 1993, p. 31.). Certainly, people may deem different “doings and beings” to be valuable. Functionings can be very simple things like being well-fed, being healthy or literate, but can also mean more complex components of life, such as being graduated, taking part in the life of the community, having self-respect or appearing in public without shame.

The “capability of a person reflects the alternative combinations of functionings the person can achieve, and from which he or she can choose one collection” (Sen 1993, p. 31.).

Thus, capabilities are the full set of attainable alternative lives, they show what people are actually able to do or be.

The distinction between functioning and capability is enormously important. Not just achievements matter but freedoms to achieve also. The freedom that a person is free to further his or her own goals (whatever goals they regard as important) is called agency. An agent in the CA is “someone who acts and brings about change” (Sen 1999, 65), who is not just a passive recipient, but takes an active role in shaping his or her own, or his or her community’s well-being (Olsaretti 2003). Within the CA, humans are not just strict maximizers of narrowly defined self-interest. Individuals have broader values, like sympathy for other persons, or commitment to ethical norms.

In the literature there are two main arguments why we should give significance to agency. First, agency has an intrinsic value. The opportunity to be able to pursuit our own goals and make individual or collective choices, is usually considered to be valuable. Second, agency has instrumental importance: an agent can facilitate the realization of valued outcomes. In other words not just the achievement but also the way how we achieve matters.

That is why we have to make distinction between functioning and capability. Capabilities are a set of alternative doings and beings one can actually achieve. But it is not equal with the most valued functioning. The opportunity to choose from alternatives is valuable in itself (Sen 1999).

(5)

In the capability approach a key analytical distinction has to be made between means and ends. It is not satisfactory to focus our attention solely on the means (instrumental freedoms) one can utilize to achieve valuable functioning. What a person can achieve with a definite amount of means or resources depends on many circumstances and facts, which are called conversation factors. The conversation from means to ends is highly influenced by different factors like: metabolism, physical condition, sex, age, intelligence, public policies, social norms and hierarchies; environmental circumstances as physical and built environment, climate or pollution.

Therefore in order to be able to asses well-being, beside instrumental freedoms, conversation factors and opportunities for agency has to be considered as well. On the top of this collective decisions has to be made, since different individual may deem different “doings and beings” to be important. A community or society first has to determine which functionings are important (they will serve as the informational basis of the evaluation). Then the relative importance of the valuable functionings compared to each other and the opportunities that are not chosen must be determined. Finally, the weight that is placed on capabilities compared to any other relevant considerations must be decided (Sen 1993, 1999).

The complexity of the task may seem to be a drawback of CA. However, it is probably a smaller problem than reducing the evaluation to the maximization of a single homogenous thing (Sen 1999).

Some theorists of the capability approach provide a list of valuable capabilities.

Nussbaum (2011) compiled an exact catalog of basic capabilities, and argues that everyone would accept that list after deliberation1. Sen refuses to offer such a list, and does not judge the relative importance of capabilities as opposed to functionings either. He argues that every community or society should decide themselves the most important capabilities through some kind of deliberative process (Sen 1999).

3. The informational basis of innovation policy in the capability approach

The informational basis of innovation policies based on evolutionary thinking and the innovation systems approach embraces all those elements that influence the emergence and

1 The ten central human capabilities according to Nussbaum are the following: life; bodily health; bodily integrity; senses; imagination and thought; emotions; practical reason; affiliation; other species; play; and control over one’s environment (Nussbaum 2011).

(6)

diffusion of innovations. This set of information allows judging the ability of a country, region or sector to speed up technological change.

However, in the capability-approach this set of information is not necessarily sufficient.

As we have already mentioned, the contribution to economic growth does not necessarily justify innovation policy within this framework. In order to be able to depict the set of information required for evaluative judgements in the capability approach, we must have a closer look at the relation between technological change and well-being.

The examination of the link between technological change and the capability approach is a relatively new field of inquiry. However, the literature of the issue is rapidly widening, which is signalled by the special issue of the journal “Ethics and Information Technology”

(June, 2011), or the volume “The Capability Approach, Technology and Design” edited by Ilse Oosterlaken and Jeroen van den Hoven, which bunches the works of several scholars dealing with this issue (Oosterlaken – van den Hoven 2012).

Most of the papers connecting the fields of technology and the capability approach primarily aim to draw conclusions for engineering and technical sciences (Johnstone 2007, Oosterlaken 2009, 2012a, Nichols – Dong 2012). However it is increasingly articulated that both fields may benefit from the connection (van den Hoven 2012). Accordingly, certain papers shed light on how the capability approach may benefit from dealing with technology (Oosterlaken 2011, Zheng – Sthal 2011).

Most of the pertinent works so far have focused on individual capabilities. They posited research questions, such as: how can new technologies contribute to the expansion of capabilities, considering the personal heterogeneities and the differences in the environment.

This has been analysed in connection with certain new artefacts or technological fields (Oosterlaken 2012a).

These papers did not really pay attention to the problem of collective decisions2. However, technologies may affect certain individuals or groups in a different manner. Hence, for our purpose the focus of studying the link between technological change and the CA must be shifted. In order to underpin policies, technological change must be judged from the perspective of the community (society). Within the capability approach technological change affects well-being in a complex way. We attempt here to systematize these relations (Table 1.).

2There are certainly exceptions as well (Lawson 2010, Fernandez-Baldor et al. 2012).

(7)

Table 1. The relation between technological change and well-being in the capability approach Instrumental freedoms

Converting opportunities into valuable “doings and

beings”

Agency

Technological change alters the volume of available resources, and alters their allocation as well.

Technological change may contribute to the expansion of the capabilities of certain individuals or groups, while leaving the capabilities of others unchanged, or may even result in the degradation of certain capabilities.

A proportion of the available resources must be devoted for defending against the “side effects”

of technological change.

Technological systems may significantly diminish the possibilities of agency.

Individuals’ or groups’ ability to adapt to the new reality induced by technological change may differ.

The moral judgement of the emerging new capabilities is necessary.

Source: own construction

Technological change influences all the three major building blocks of well-being: the available instrumental freedoms, the conversion of these means into valuable “doings and beings”, and also the possibilities of agency. It is apparent that technological change is an extremely important, or is even the main factor of economic growth today. Since the seminal works of Solow (1956, 1957) this has been widely argued. In a utilitarian tradition, where income is used as a proxy for preference satisfaction, growth is the very evidence that such a shift is necessarily beneficial on the whole: the winners would be able to compensate losers, and still would be in a better position than before. However this argument seems to be problematic from the perspective of capability approach (Sen 1979, Hausmann – McPherson 1996).

Within the capability approach the widening of economic opportunities requires closer scrutiny. First, it is not apparent that more wealth contributes to increased well-being. In case other freedoms were sacrificed for increased growth, than the judgement of the shift becomes ambiguous. Second, different groups do not benefit equally from growth, which may change the allocation of wealth. If growth is accompanied by increasing inequalities, than it may result in welfare loss on the whole. The fact that winners could compensate losers does not infer that they actually will. On the top of this, the same amount of wealth may contribute to different sets of valuable “doings and beings” in case of different individuals or groups, therefore the allocation is not a by-issue.

Technology is affects the ability to convert means into ends. New technologies may be adequate for some, while useless, or dysfunctional for others (Osoterlaken 2009). For example a bicycle will not bring about any valuable actions a disabled can do (Sen 1999, Osoterlaken

(8)

2012b), or a mobile phone will not contribute to the expansion of capabilities where there is no signal.

Besides, new technologies may also reduce the set of valuable “doings and beings” one can achieve by their resources. New technologies necessarily bring about unforeseen effects (side-effects). As Feenberg (2010) phrased, when we use technologies, we act on a system to which we ourselves belong. Within this complex system our actions return to us in some form. These effects cannot be fully foreseen or eliminated, which is a direct consequence of the nature of complex systems (Foster 2006). Therefore a proportion of our income must be devoted for defending against the “side-effects” of new technologies (e.g. we must buy sunscreen, or bottled water, pay the costs of hazardous waste treatment). And there are a lot of effects against which we are unable to defend, and that decreases well-being (e.g. the locking of certain areas contaminated by radioactivity for decades apparently decreases the well-being of former residents).

Technological change also affects the opportunities of agency. The whole stream of the substantivist philosophy on technology demonstrated how modern technological societies constrain the opportunities of civil agency (Marcuse 1965, Foucault 1978, Ellul 1980).

Recently social constructivists have put forth a bunch of examples on how new technologies incorporate social relations (Pinch – Bijker 1987). Building on the social constructivist arguments Feenberg (1999) posits that technologies encode ideologies and hegemonies. In contrast to the substantivist arguments, he believes that technologies may also be constructed to overcome the existing hegemonies. Nevertheless once certain values and social relations become encoded in technological designs, they will shape the possibilities of agency.

Technological change results in the emergence of a new reality to which individuals, groups or societies must adapt. For example the spread of internet has brought about electronic public administration. Actors must devote time and wealth to learn to cope with the new reality. But individuals’ our groups’ ability to adapt to changes may differ. The ability to carry out this kind of agency may significantly shape the way technological change affects well-being.

Finally, to be able to make collective decisions in the capability approach, one of the main tasks is to decide which capabilities are thought to be valuable (or more valuable than others). One of the main differences between the capability approach and other welfare approaches is that CA makes this value judgement explicit and draws attention to its unavoidability.

(9)

Therefore within the CA one must ask whether the capabilities brought about by new technologies are valuable or not. In other words the ethical evaluation of new technologies is necessary (Oosterlaken 2012a). The same technology may be acceptable for certain societies or groups, while inacceptable for others. The opportunity to carry out such evaluative judgements, and to shape technological change by such acts may significantly affect the relation between new technologies and well-being.

4. How would the new informational basis differ?

The commitment to the capability approach infers shift in the axioms of innovation policy. The ultimate objective would be the contribution to the widening of capabilities, instead of contributing to growth in economic performance, productivity or employment. But would this also result in a change regarding the set of information required for the design and evaluation of innovation policies? In present section we attempt to demonstrate how the informational basis of policy would differ in the CA from that of the growth-centred utilitarian view.

From a welfare economics perspective the informational basis of the growth-centred view has two very important features. One is aggregation, or “sum-ranking” as Sen (1999) would call it. By relying on the concept of growth, they interpret welfare gains on the average (per capita), and the allocation of welfare is not examined. The second feature is pecuniary evaluation: they use money (real income) as a proxy for welfare. This allows to disregard, or to reduce to a common denominator (per capita GDP) many of the important features of technological change.

Within the capability approach this excluded set of information gains importance. In this respect the informational basis of innovation policy in the CA is not entirely different, but wider. We attempt to demonstrate the importance of the excluded set of information alongside certain selected features of technological change.

The concept of creative destruction argues that while new structures are created in the course of technological change, the existing structures are converted or wither (Schumpeter 1950). Within a growth-centred view the average (per capita) change is in the focus. But in the CA we cannot disregard that winners and losers are created – at least in the short term).

One might still argue that in the long run everyone may benefit, but it still resumes the ability to convert the new opportunities into functionings and the ability to act as an agent (to adapt to changes). On the top of this, different groups are able to utilize the new opportunities to a

(10)

different extent. Therefore in the CA we need to know how additional wealth is allocated within the society.

On the top of this several empirical studies show that people compare their position to certain reference groups (Layard 2006, Costanza et al. 2007), and, hence, if someone’s position has remained unchanged while new opportunities have emerged for all the others, then in fact their position has become worse instead of remaining unchanged. This is also the reason why inequalities matter

Due to creative destruction, while new ways to satisfy needs emerge, certain former choice options are abolished. Within the utilitarian view, these contrasting effects can easily be compared by choosing income as a common denominator, and growth itself is the evidence that gains overcompensate losses.

From the point of view of the capability approach we cannot by-pass the comparison that easily. The creation of new opportunities does not necessarily infer the ability to convert them into valuable funcionings (e.g. we may not have the income to pay for the most sophisticated medical therapies, we may not benefit from faster means of transportation because the lack of infrastructure). On the top of this, new and lost opportunities cannot always be easily compared (or be compared at all). In the course of change, such options may be abolished that we do not necessarily value in money, but which are still important components of well-being.

Technological change in many cases increases labour productivity while leaving capital productivity relatively unchanged. This can be well interpreted by Hick’s induced innovation hypothesis (Jaffe et al. 2003, Ruttan 1997). This may result in a tendency where enterprises combine a relatively small number of workers with a large amount of capital, which may (but not necessarily) change the allocation of incomes, and thus increase inequalities.

Another important trait of technological change is that it creates “side-effects” in parallel with creating wealth (Feenberg 2010). These effects are to a certain extent unrecognizable at the time of the introduction of the innovation (Beck 1992, Hansson 2005).

There are at least three reasons for this.

First, as evolutionary economics argues, due to positive feedback mechanisms the course of technological change is unpredictable (Arthur 1989, 1990, Nelson 1995). Second, during the prediction of the potential effects of new technologies we can rely only on past experience, but innovations may generate entirely new processes (Schot 2001). Third, change can be reflexive: new technologies may alter the complex situation within which they have occurred, and thus they may alter their own possible effects (Beck 1992, Feenberg 2010).

(11)

Actually, many of today’s innovations are developed to solve problems caused by earlier inventions.

Therefore “side-effects” are incentives for subsequent innovation. From the growth- centred view this phenomenon is perceived as the speeding up of technological change, which is fairly beneficial. Within this aspect, side-effects cannot really be recognized, since the current GDP measures disregard them. But in the CA a direct corollary of their presence is that a given proportion of our means has to be used for defending ourselves against side- effects. Or if this is not possible they just simply decrease our capabilities. On the top of this

“side-effects” can be allocated unequally among the groups and members of society. This can result in a situation where most of the risks are allocated to those with the least wealth.

Finally, the speeding up of technological change is interpreted as faster growth in TFP (and in economic output) from a growth-centred utilitarian view. It is not that simple, however, from the capability approach. On the one hand, faster technological change implies more intense production of side-effects and leaves less time to recognize them. On the other hand, since economic and social structures are incessantly altered, actors must adapt to these changes. The faster the change is, the quicker the adaptation that is required. But people’s, groups’ or regions’ ability to do so may differ.

Therefore, we can argue that the conventional informational basis of innovation policy leaves several aspects of technological change unconsidered. If welfare is not equated with per capita GDP, but interpreted as the expansion of capabilities, than the excluded set of information is relevant for policy evaluation.

5. The outlines of innovation policy in the capability approach: towards a really differentiated innovation policy

Today’s innovation policies heavily build on the systems of innovation approach. In the last two and a half decades the concept has been very influential, and has significantly affected the economics of innovation literature and also policy-making (Lundvall et al. 2002, Fagerberg – Sappraster 2011). The approach provides a comprehensive framework for understanding and examining the phenomenon of technological change.

As many of its advocates posit, the borders of innovation systems are not sharp, system boundaries are to a given extent arbitrary (Nelson – Rosenberg 1993, Edquist 2005). Recently Lundvall et al. (2002) called for the broadening of the boundaries of examination in order to

(12)

become capable of encompassing elements that have gained increased importance in the learning economy, or to incorporate ecological issues.

We also called for the widening of the informational basis in the previous sections in order to be able to reflect the well-being effects of technological change. The systems of innovation approach, as a methodology, is not questioned. System failures could be recognized as rationales for policy making in the capability approach as well, however the CA sheds light on different system failures recognized so far.

Table: The outlines of innovation policy in the capability approach Rational for policy making The failure of the innovation system to contribute to the expansion of

capabilities:

- technological change creates wealth to the expense of other freedoms, - technological change creates opportunities that cannot be effectively

used to achieve valuable “functionings” for the community.

System failures Institutions, organizations and links fail to generate and diffuse knowledge:

- that contributes to the identification and alteration of ideologies, hegemonies lying behind current innovation processes,

- that would be necessary to identify the feedbacks of the system on which we act on when we use technologies (fail to encompass the

“side-effects” of technology),

- on the ability of the society to adapt to changes,

- on the moral judgement of the society and incorporate this information into innovation processes.

Aspects of the

technological phenomenon to be examined

The artefact gains importance beside the currently examined aspects of the technological phenomenon, such as:

- the technique,

- the sociotechnical system of manufacture, - and the socio-technical system of use.

Reflecting to the differences of systems

Beside the uniqueness of innovation systems, the differences with regard:

- the capabilities deemed to be valuable, - the factors of conversation,

- the ability to adapt to changes, - the possibilities of agency,

- and the moral judgement on new technologies should also be considered.

Forming of innovation policy

Beside unpredictability, uncertainty and bounded rationality policy making should reflect the fact, that:

- the required set of knowledge is scattered amongst a large number of local actors (including non-experts),

- innovation policy necessitates value commitment.

Source: own construction

We demonstrated that different individuals or groups may be affected by technological change entirely differently, which also infers that they do not judge the well-being effects of

(13)

technological change in the same way. Within a society there may exist several (sometimes competing or even contrasting) viewpoints about the operation of innovation system that contributes to well-being (the extension of capabilities).

The rationale for innovation policy making in the capability approach is the failure of the innovation system to contribute to the expansion of capabilities (Table 2.). The direct corollary of this formulation is that the particular objectives of innovation policy are not fixed for once and for all. They will obviously differ in space and time, since they are formulated as results of social choices, where the competing or contrasting viewpoints are negotiated.

The failure of the innovation system to contribute to the expansion of capabilities may be interpreted alongside the “building blocks” of well-being. Either technological change creates wealth to the expense of other freedoms, or it creates opportunities that cannot be effectively used to achieve valuable “functionings” for the community. The third major problem arises in case it reduces the opportunity for agency.

In the contemporary innovation systems literature the failures of systems are originated in the inappropriate operation (or the lack) of certain organizations, institutions and links (Edquist 2002). Within the CA system failures may also be expressed by referring to these system elements. However, in this case, these elements of the innovation systems are not only required to generate, diffuse and utilize technologies; we must also ask what kind of information, knowledge or technology is transmitted. If a society expressed its dissatisfaction with the current processes, than it would probably formulate failures such as:

- Institutions, organizations and links fail to generate and diffuse knowledge that contributes to the identification and alteration of ideologies, hegemonies lying behind current innovation processes.

- Institutions, organizations and links fail to generate and diffuse knowledge that would be necessary to identify the feedbacks of the system on which we act on when we use technologies (fail to encompass the “side-effects” of technology).

- Institutions, organization and links fail to generate and diffuse knowledge on the ability of the society to adapt to changes.

- Institutions, organization and links fail to generate and diffuse knowledge on the moral judgement of the society on the capabilities (and thus technologies) deemed to be valuable, and incorporate this information into innovation processes.

The capability approach draws attention to the importance of the artefacts (technological design). Two and a half decades ago Pinch and Bijker (1987) condemned

(14)

innovation studies carried out by economists. They argued that “in the economic analysis of technological innovation everything is included that might be expected to influence innovation, expect any discussion of the technology itself” (Pinch – Bijker 1987, p. 21.). They disregarded many of the prior achievement of economics in this field (Nelson – Winter 1977, Dosi 1982, Rosenberg 1982), and since then the economics of innovation has developed a sophisticated picture on the technological phenomenon (Nelson – Winter 1982, Nelson 1993, Lundvall 1992). However, the artefact has not become a subjects of analysis.

Within the capability approach this aspect of technological phenomenon cannot remain a “black box”, since artefacts encode social relations and moral judgements, and are shaped by social processes (Feenberg 1999, Winner 2003). Innovation policy should not avoid the question that what kind of artefacts are brought about in the course of technological change, since the design affects well-being and is subject to social judgments.

Innovation polices based on the arguments of the CA, would be really differentiated policies. The systems of innovation literature calls for differentiated innovation policies, in order to reflect the (historically developed) unique nature of innovation systems (Edquist 2002, Tödtling – Trippl 2005). However, it is not just the innovation systems that are different among countries (regions, sectors or technological fields). Communities may differ with regard the capabilities deemed to be valuable. Due to environmental and personal differences, agents may achieve different valuable functionings by new technologies. The ability to adapt to changes, the possibilities of agency and the moral judgement on new technologies may also be entirely different. Within the world of CA these important peculiarities should all be considered during the design, implementation and evaluation of innovation policies. And this is exactly what could make innovation policies really differentiated, since the set of information required for policy making is – beside being specific to a given community or society – incorporates knowledge elements that are possessed by local actors.

Our above arguments infer that in the capability approach innovation policies should deal with such phenomena that are thought to be beyond the scope of today’s studies. The field for policy making would be a “post-normal” situation. According to Ravetz (2004) the style of scientific examination and policy making is “post-normal” when facts are uncertain (they are open for different interpretations), values are in dispute, stakes are high (complex structures, interests and hegemonies are in question), and still decisions are urgent.

The capability approach shed light on these very peculiarities of dealing with technological change. These characteristics are not novel; the difference is that the CA makes this framework explicit. Evolutionary economics has a long tradition in dealing with

(15)

situations of uncertainty, unpredictability and bounded rationality (Metcalfe 1994, 1995, Witt 2003). What is added here is on the one hand, that the required set of knowledge is scattered amongst a large number of local actors (including non-experts), on the other hand innovation policy necessitates value commitment. However these differences are not subtle, and have basic consequences on the forming of policy making.

Summary and Looking Ahead

Present paper examined innovation policy making within the framework of the capability approach. Today’s innovation policies ultimately aim to contribute to economic growth, productivity growth or employment. These are objectives that are formulated in the political arena; therefore the examination of their adequacy is beyond the scope of the innovation policy literature.

However, it seems to be very improbable, that the formulation of these objectives is fully external. We cannot assume that these aims are moulded in the political arena without any reference to economic theorizing on welfare. Within the dominating utilitarian traditions of economics, growth in economic outputs, productivity or employment almost necessarily leads to increased welfare. But not so in the capability approach, the most influential contemporary welfare tradition, which is hallmarked by the Nobel-laureate Amartya Sen.

Present paper argued that, although the “utilitarianism versus capability approach”

debate occurs beyond the scope of economic theorizing on innovation and innovation policies, the consequences might affect the very gist of this stream of literature. We choose capability approach as a starting point, and examined whether this shift in the underlying “axioms”

resulted in a change regarding the set of information needed for the design, implementation and evaluation of innovation policies. We concluded that switching to the capability approach would result in a sea-change in the informational basis and also in the main characteristics of innovation policy making. While the systems of innovation approach, as a methodology, would remain useful in the capability approach, the reinterpretation of certain concepts (such as system failures) might be necessary.

Finally we must ask how the economics of innovation and innovation policy could benefit from the capability approach. First, CA provides an incentive and a way to broaden the boundaries of the analysis, which seems to be in line with the intentions of certain salient advocates of the innovation systems (Lundvall et al. 2002).

(16)

Second, within the framework of the CA we may depict a more detailed picture on the effects of technical change. CA sheds light on the complexity of this phenomenon by decomposing well-being to instrumental freedoms, conversation factors and agency. This may provide a deeper understanding of the success of certain countries (regions) and the lagging behind of others. Creating greater wealth on the average through technological change is not sufficient; it must be converted to valuable “doings and beings”, which heavily depend on the possibilities for agency.

Third, empirical works could also benefit from this thought. The correspondence between technological change and the countries’ (regions’) success might be better understood, if we differentiated the ability to generate and diffuse innovations, and the ability to adapt to the new reality induced by technical change; or made distinction between innovations that actually create new capabilities, and innovations that provide solutions for problems induced by earlier novelties (in other words the wealth created by technological change and the costs of defending ourselves against the side-effects of change).

Finally, CA could help to make the post-normal situation, in which innovation policy occurs, visible. A large set of knowledge that is required for innovation policy making within the CA is possessed by non-experts. Today, innovation policy (implicitly) builds on assumptions about these knowledge elements (e.g. the faster the technological change, the more welcome it is, the effects compensate for side-effects, artefacts can be handled as black boxes, or moral judgements on technology are irrelevant), but these implicit assumptions are either not tested empirically, or seem to contradict to other theories. Within the CA it becomes apparent that innovation policy cannot succeed without this set of knowledge. The incorporation of this idea into the forming of innovation policy could be perceived as a way to reduce policy failures.

References

Alkire, S. – Qizilbash, M. – Comom, F. (2008): Introduction. In Alkire, S. – Qizilbash, M. – Comon, F. (eds):

The Capability Approach. Concepts, Measures and Applications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Alkire, S. (2002): Dimensions of Human Development. World Development, 30, 2,2 pp. 181-205.

Anderson, E. S. (1999): What is the Point of Equality? Ethics, 109, 2, pp. 287-337.

Arthur, W. B. (1989): Competing Technologies, Increasing Returns and Lock-in by Historical Events. Economic Journal, 99, pp. 116-131.

Arthur, W. B. (1990): Positive Feedbacks in the Economy. Scientific American, 262, 2, pp. 92-99.

(17)

Beck, U. (1992) Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. SAGE Publication, London – Thousand Oaks – New Delhi.

Costanza, R. – Fisher, B. – Ali, S. – Beer, C. – Bond, L. – Boumans, R. – Danigelis, N. L. – Dickinson, J. – Elliot, C. – Farley, J. – Gayer, D. E. – Glenn, L. M. – Hudspeth, T. – Mahoney, D. – McCahill, L. – McIntosh, B. – Reed, B. – Rizvi, S. A. T. – Rizzo, D. M. – Simpatico, T. – Snapp, R. (2007) Quality of Life: An Approach Integrating Opportunities, Human Needs, and Subjective Well-being. Ecological Economics, 61, 2-3, pp. 267-276.

Dosi, G. (1982): Technological Paradigms and Technological Trajectories: A Suggested Interpretation of the Determinants and Directions of Technical Change. Research Policy, 11, 3, pp. 147-162.

Edquist, C. (2002): Innovation Policy. A Systemic Approach. In Archiburgi, D – Lundvall, B. A. (eds): The Globalizing Learning Economy. Oxford University Press, Oxford – New York, pp. 219-238.

Edquist, C. (2005): Systems of innovation approaches. Their emergence and characteristics. In Edquist, C. (ed.):

Systems of innovation. Technologies, institutions and organizations. Routledge, London – New York, pp.

1-35.

Ellul, J. (1980): The technological system. The Continuum Publishing Corporation, New York.

Fagerberg, J. – Sapprasert, K. (2011): National Innovation Systems: The Emergence of a New Approach.

Science and Public Policy, 38, 9, pp. 669-679.

Feenberg, A. (1999): Questioning technology. Routledge, London – New York.

Feenberg, A. (2010): Ten paradoxes of technology. Techné, 14, 1, pp. 3-15.

Fernandez-Baldor, A. – Hueso, A. – Boni, A. (2012): From individuality to collectivity: the challenges for technology-oriented development projects. In Oosterlaken, I. – van den Hoven, J. (eds): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design. Springer, Dordrecht – Heidelberg – New York – London, pp. 135- 152.

Foucault, M. (1978): Discipline and punish: the birth of the prison. Pantheon, New York.

Foster, J. (2006): Why is economics not a complex systems science? Journal of Economic Issues, 40, 4, pp.

1069-1091.

Gasper, D. (2007): What is the capability approach? Its core, rationale, partners and dangers. The Journal of Socio-Economics, 36, pp. 335-359.

Hansson, S. O. (2005): The epistemology of technological risk. Techné, 9, 2, pp. 68-80.

Hausman, D. M. – McPherson, M. S. (1996): Economic Analysis and Moral Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Hoven, J. van den (2012): Human capabilities and technology. In Oosterlaken, I. – van den Hoven, J. (eds): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design. Springer, Dordrecht – Heidelberg – New York – London, pp. 27-36.

Jaffe, A. B. – Newell, R. G. – Stavins, R. N. (2003): Technological Change and the Environment. In Mäler, K.

G. – Vincent, J. R. (eds): Handbook of Environmental Economics. Volume 1: Environmental Degradation and Institutional Responses. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 461-516.

Johnstone, J. (2007): Technology as empowerment: a capability approach to computer ethics. Ethics and Information Technology, 9, pp. 73-87.

(18)

Kleine, S. (2009): What is technology. In Scharff, R. C. – Dusek, V. (eds): Philosophy of technology. The technological condition. Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp. 208-210.

Lawson, C. (2010): Technology and the extension of human capabilities. Journal of the Theory of Social Behaviour, 40, 2, pp. 207-223.

Layard, R. (2006) Happiness: Lessons from a New Science. Penguin, London.

Lundvall, B. A. (ed.) (1992): National Systems of Innovation: Towards a Theory of Innovation and Interactive Learning. Pinter, London.

Lundvall, B. A. – Johnson, B. – Andersen, E. S. – Dalum, B. (2002) National systems of production, innovation and competence building. Research Policy, 31, 2, pp. 213-231.

Marcuse, H. (1964): One-dimensional man. Beacon, Boston.

Metcalfe, S. J. (1994): Evolutionary Economics and Technology Policy. The Economic Journal, 104, 425, pp.

931-944.

Metcalfe, S. J. (1995): Technology systems and technology policy in an evolutionary framework. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 19, 1, pp. 25-46.

Nelson, R. R. (ed.) (1993): National innovation systems. A comparative analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford – New York.

Nelson, R. R. (1995): Recent Evolutionary Theorizing about Economic Change. Journal of Economic Literature, 33, 3, pp. 48-90.

Nelson, R. R. – Rosenberg, N. (1993): Technical innovation and national systems. In Nelson, R. R. (eds.):

National innovation systems. A comparative analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford – New York, pp.

3-21.

Nelson, R. R. – Winter, S. G. (1977): In search of a useful theory of innovation. Research Policy, 6, 1, pp. 36-76.

Nelson, R. R – Winter, S. G. (1982): An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Belknap Harvard, Cambridge, MA – London, UK.

Nichols, C. – Dong, A. (2012): Re-conceptualizing design through the capability approach. In Oosterlaken, I. – van den Hoven, J. (eds): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design. Springer, Dordrecht – Heidelberg – New York – London, pp. 189-202.

Nussbaum, M. (2011): Creating capabilities: the human development approach. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

Olsaretti, S. (2003): Endorsement and freedom in Amartya Sen's capability approach. In 3rd Conference on the Capability Approach. Pavia.

Oosterlaken, I. (2009): Design for development: a capability approach. Design Issues, 25, 4, pp. 91-102.

Oosterlaken, I. (2011): Inserting technology in the relational ontology of Sen’s capability approach. Journal of Human Development and Capabilities, 12, 3, pp. 425-432.

Osoterlaken , I. (2012a): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design: Taking Stock and Looking Ahead.

In Oosterlaken, I. – van den Hoven, J. (eds): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design. Springer, Dordrecht – Heidelberg – New York – London, pp. 3-26.

Osterlaken, I. (2012b): Inappropriate artefact, unjust design? Human diversity as a key concern in the capability approach and inclusive design. In Oosterlaken, I. – van den Hoven, J. (eds): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design. Springer, Dordrecht – Heidelberg – New York – London, pp.223-244.

(19)

Oosterlaken, I. – van den Hoven, J. (eds) (2012): The Capability Approach, Technology and Design. Springer, Dordrecht – Heidelberg – New York – London.

Pinch, T. J. – Bijker, W. E. (1987): The social construction of facts and artefacts: or how the sociology of science and the sociology of technology might benefit each other. In Bijker, W. E. – Hughes, T. P. – Pinch, T. J. (eds): The Social Constructio of Technological Systems. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. pp.

17-40.

Ravetz, J. (2004): The post-normal science of precaution. Futures, 36, pp. 347-357.

Robeyns, I. (2006): The Capability Approach in Practice. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 14, 3, pp. 351- 376.

Rosenberg, N. (1982): Inside the black box: technology and economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Ruttan, V. W. (1997): Induced Innovation, Evolutionary Theory and Path Dependence: Sources of Technical Change. The Economic Journal, 107, 444, pp. 1520-1529.

Sen, A. K. (1979): The Welfare Basis of Real-Income Comparisons: A Survey. Journal of Economic Literature, 17, 1, pp. 1-45.

Sen, A. K. (1993): Capability and Well-being. In Nussbaum, M. C. – Sen A. K. The Quality of Life. Clarendon Press, Oxford. pp. 30-53.

Sen, A. K. (1999): Development as Freedom. Oxford University Press, Oxford – New York.

Sen, A. K. (2005): On Ethics and Economics. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford.

Schot, J. (2001) Towards New Forms of Participatory Technology Development. Technology Analysis and Strategic Management, 13, 1, pp. 39-52.

Schumpeter, J. (1950): Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. Third edition. Harper and Row, New York.

Solow, R. (1956): A contribution to the theory of economic growth. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 70, pp. 65- 94.

Solow, R. M. (1957): Technical Change and the Aggregate Production Function. Review of Economics and Statistics, 39, 3, pp. 312-320.

Tödtling, F. – Trippl, M. (2005): One size fit all? Towards a differentiated regional innovation policy approach.

Research Policy, 34, 8, pp. 1203-1209.

Winner, L. (2003): Social Constructivism: Opening the black box and finding it empty. In Scharff, R. C. – Dusek, V. (eds): Philosophy of technology. The technological condition. Blackwell Publishing, Malden – Oxford – Victoria. pp. 233-243.

Witt, U. (2003): Economic Policy Making in an Evolutionary Perspective. Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 13, 2, pp. 77-94.

Zheng, Y. – Stahl, B. C. (2011): Technology, capabilities and critical perspectives: what can critical theory contribute to Sen’s capability approach. Ethics and Information Technology, 13, 2, pp. 69-80.

Ábra

Table 1. The relation between technological change and well-being in the capability approach  Instrumental freedoms

Hivatkozások

KAPCSOLÓDÓ DOKUMENTUMOK

If we want to answer the research question, "Does Provision of Smart Services depend on cooperation flexi- bility, innovation flexibility, innovation performance and

This view of freedom as possessing contributory value suggests a particular interpretation of the way the notions of capability and functioning are to be incorporated into

So the main difference between an instrumental approach and the capability based LED is the following: the former focuses on the instruments – like income,

Being a conditional, the first premiss asserts that we have to justify the denial of every potential defeater of the justification of a proposition in order to be justified

Therefore, if we encode the claim information for a portfolio of MTPL policies into a claimBool variable where True = the policy caused claim in a given year and False = the

Thus, based on the statistical outcomes and the analysis of documents, we identified five policy gaps affecting sustainability: (1) a lack of an ecological approach, (2)

• Our common understanding: increased innovation performance results is a more advantageous

Európai Bizottság (2002): Innovation tomorrow, Innovation policy and the regulatory framework: Making innovation an integral part of the broader structural agenda.. Innovation papers